Virtue in Smiles
October 19, 2014James Henry Leigh Hunt |
Leigh Hunt (1784-1859)
Vol. 27, pp. 285-295 of
The Harvard Classics
Weep if you must. It
is far better than to repress your tears. But Leigh Hunt finds
greater virtue in cheerfulness. Fanciful and graceful - his writings
exerted a wholesome influence on all nineteenth century journalism.
(James Henry Leigh
Hunt born Oct. 19, 1784.)
Deaths
of Little Children
A GRECIAN philosopher
being asked why he wept for the death of his son, since the sorrow
was in vain, replied, “I weep on that account.” And his answer
became his wisdom. It is only for sophists to contend that we, whose
eyes contain the fountains of tears, need never give way to them. It
would be unwise not to do so on some occasions. Sorrow unlocks them
in her balmy moods. The first bursts may be bitter and overwhelming;
but the soil on which they pour would be worse without them. They
refresh the fever of the soul—the dry misery which parches the
countenance into furrows, and renders us liable to our most terrible
“flesh-quakes.”
There are
sorrows, it is true, so great, that to give them some of the ordinary
vents is to run a hazard of being overthrown. These we must rather
strengthen ourselves to resist, or bow quietly and drily down, in
order to let them pass over us, as the traveller does the wind of the
desert. But where we feel that tears would relieve us, it is false
philosophy to deny ourselves at least that first refreshment; and it
is always false consolation to tell people that because they cannot
help a thing, they are not to mind it. The true way is, to let them
grapple with the unavoidable sorrow, and try to win it into
gentleness by a reasonable yielding. There are griefs so gentle in
their very nature that it would be worse than false heroism to refuse
them a tear. Of this kind are the deaths of infants. Particular
circumstances may render it more or less advisable to indulge in
grief for the loss of a little child; but, in general, parents should
be no more advised to repress their first tears on such an occasion,
than to repress their smiles towards a child surviving, or to indulge
in any other sympathy. It is an appeal to the same gentle tenderness;
and such appeals are never made in vain. The end of them is an
acquittal from the harsher bonds of affliction—from the typing down
of the spirit to one melancholy idea.
It is the
nature of tears of this kind, however strongly they may gush forth,
to run into quiet waters at last. We cannot easily, for the whole
course of our lives, think with pain of any good and kind person whom
we have lost. It is the divine nature of their qualities to conquer
pain and death itself; to turn the memory of them into pleasure; to
survive with a placid aspect in our imaginations. We are writing at
this moment just opposite a spot which contains the grave of one
inexpressibly dear to us. We see from our window the trees about it,
and the church spire. The green fields lie around. The clouds are
travelling overhead, alternately taking away the sunshine and
restoring it. The vernal winds, piping of the flowery summer-time,
are nevertheless calling to mind the far-distant and dangerous ocean,
which the heart that lies in that grave had many reasons to think of.
And yet the sight of this spot does not give us pain. So far from it,
it is the existence of that grave which doubles every charm of the
spot; which links the pleasures of our childhood and manhood
together; which puts a hushing tenderness in the winds, and a patient
joy upon the landscape; which seems to unite heaven and earth,
mortality and immortality, the grass of the tomb and the grass of the
green field; and gives a more maternal aspect to the whole kindness
of nature. It does not hinder gaiety itself. Happiness was what its
tenant, through all her troubles, would have diffused. To diffuse
happiness, and to enjoy it, is not only carrying on her wishes, but
realising her hopes; and gaiety, freed from its only pollutions,
malignity and want of sympathy, is but a child playing about the
knees of its mother.
The
remembered innocence and endearments of a child stand us instead of
virtues that have died older. Children have not exercised the
voluntary offices of friendship; they have not chosen to be kind and
good to us; nor stood by us, from conscious will, in the hour of
adversity. But they have shared their pleasures and pains with us as
well as they could; the interchange of good offices between us has,
of necessity, been less mingled with the troubles of the world; the
sorrow arising from their death is the only one which we can
associate with their memories. These are happy thoughts that cannot
die. Our loss may always render them pensive; but they will not
always be painful. It is a part of the benignity of Nature that pain
does not survive like pleasure, at any time, much less where the
cause of it is an innocent one. The smile will remain reflected by
memory, as the moon reflects the light upon us when the sun has gone
into heaven.
When
writers like ourselves quarrel with earthly pain (we mean writers of
the same intentions, without implying, of course, anything about
abilities or otherwise), they are misunderstood if they are supposed
to quarrel with pains of every sort. This would be idle and
effeminate. They do not pretend, indeed, that humanity might not
wish, if it could, to be entirely free from pain; for it endeavours,
at all times, to turn pain into pleasure: or at least to set off the
one with the other, to make the former a zest and the latter a
refreshment. The most unaffected dignity of suffering does this, and,
if wise, acknowledges it. The greatest benevolence towards others,
the most unselfish relish of their pleasures, even at its own
expense, does but look to increasing the general stock of happiness,
though content, if it could, to have its identity swallowed up in
that splendid contemplation. We are far from meaning that this is to
be called selfishness. We are far, indeed, from thinking so, or of so
confounding words. But neither is it to be called pain when most
unselfish, if disinterestedness by truly understood. The pain that is
in it softens into pleasure, as the darker hue of the rainbow melts
into the brighter. Yet even if a harsher line is to be drawn between
the pain and pleasure of the most unselfish mind (and ill-health, for
instance, may draw it), we should not quarrel with it if it
contributed to the general mass of comfort, and were of a nature
which general kindliness could not avoid. Made as we are, there are
certain pains without which it would be difficult to conceive certain
great and overbalancing pleasures. We may conceive it possible for
beings to be made entirely happy; but in our composition something of
pain seems to be a necessary ingredient, in order that the materials
may turn to as fine account as possible, though our clay, in the
course of ages and experience, may be refined more and more. We may
get rid of the worst earth, though not of earth itself.
Now the
liability to the loss of children—or rather what renders us
sensible of it, the occasional loss itself—seems to be one of these
necessary bitters thrown into the cup of humanity. We do not mean
that every one must lose one of his children in order to enjoy the
rest; or that every individual loss afflicts us in the same
proportion. We allude to the deaths of infants in general. These
might be as few as we could render them. But if none at all ever took
place, we should regard every little child as a man or woman secured;
and it will easily be conceived what a world of endearing cares and
hopes this security would endanger. The very idea of infancy would
lose its continuity with us. Girls and boys would be future men and
women, not present children. They would have attained their full
growth in our imaginations, and might as well have been men and women
at once. On the other hand, those who have lost an infant, are never,
as it were, without an infant child. They are the only persons who,
in one sense, retain it always, and they furnish their neighbours
with the same idea. The other children grow up to manhood and
womanhood, and suffer all the changes of mortality. This one alone is
rendered an immortal child. Death has arrested it with his kindly
harshness, and blessed it into an eternal image of youth and
innocence.
Of such as
these are the pleasantest shapes that visit our fancy and our hopes.
They are the ever-smiling emblems of joy; the prettiest pages that
wait upon imagination. Lastly, “Of these are the kingdom of
heaven.” Wherever there is a province of that benevolent and
all-accessible empire, whether on earth or elsewhere, such are the
gentle spirits that must inhabit it. To such simplicity, or the
resemblance of it, must they come. Such must be the ready confidence
of their hearts and creativeness of their fancy. And so ignorant must
they be of the “knowledge of good and evil,” losing their
discernment of that self-created trouble, by enjoying the garden
before them, and not being ashamed of what is kindly and innocent.
On the Realities of
Imagination
THERE is
not a more unthinking way of talking than to say such and such pains
and pleasures are only imaginary, and therefore to be got rid of or
under-valued accordingly. There is nothing imaginary in the common
acceptation of the word. The logic of Moses in the Vicar of
Wakefield is good argument here:—“Whatever is, is.”
Whatever touches us, whatever moves us, does touch and does move us.
We recognise the reality of it, as we do that of a hand in the dark.
We might as well say that a sight which makes us laugh, or a blow
which brings tears into our eyes, is imaginary, as that anything else
is imaginary which makes us laugh or weep. We can only judge of
things by their effects. Our perception constantly deceives us, in
things with which we suppose ourselves perfectly conversant; but our
reception of their effect is a different matter. Whether we are
materialists or immaterialists, whether things be about us or within
us, whether we think the sun is a substance, or only the image of a
divine thought, an idea, a thing imaginary, we are equally agreed as
to the notion of its warmth. But on the other hand, as this warmth is
felt differently by different temperaments, so what we call imaginary
things affect different minds. What we have to do is not to deny
their effect, because we do not feel in the same proportion, or
whether we even feel it at all; but to see whether our neighbours may
not be moved. If they are, there is, to all intents and purposes, a
moving cause. But we do not see it? No;—neither perhaps do they.
They only feel it; they are only sentient,—a word which implies the
sight given to the imagination by the feelings. But what do you mean,
we may ask in return, by seeing? Some rays of light come in contact
with the eye; they bring a sensation to it; in a word, they touch it;
and the impression left by this touch we call sight. How far does
this differ in effect from the impression left by any other touch,
however mysterious? An ox knocked down by a butcher, and a man
knocked down by a fit of apoplexy, equally feel themselves compelled
to drop. The tickling of a straw and of a comedy equally move the
muscles about the mouth. The look of a beloved eye will so thrill the
frame, that old philosophers have had recourse to a doctrine of beams
and radiant particles flying from one sight to another. In fine, what
is contact itself, and why does it affect us? There is no one cause
more mysterious than another, if we look into it.
Nor does
the question concern us like moral causes. We may be content to know
the earth by its fruits; but how to increase and improve them is a
more attractive study. If, instead of saying that the causes which
moved in us this or that pain or pleasure were imaginary, people were
to say that the causes themselves were removable, they would be
nearer the truth. When a stone trips us up, we do not fall to
disputing its existence: we put it out of the way. In like manner,
when we suffer from what is called an imaginary pain, our business is
not to canvass the reality of it. Whether there is any cause or not
in that or any other perception, or whether everything consist not in
what is called effect, it is sufficient for us that the effect is
real. Our sole business is to remove those second causes, which
always accompany the original idea. As in deliriums, for instance, it
would be idle to go about persuading the patient that he did not
behold the figures he says he does. He might reasonably ask us, if he
could, how we know anything about the matter; or how we can be sure
that in the infinite wonders of the universe certain realities may
not become apparent to certain eyes, whether diseased or not. Our
business would be to put him into that state of health in which human
beings are not diverted from their offices and comforts by a
liability to such imaginations. The best reply to his question would
be, that such a morbidity is clearly no more a fit state for a human
being than a disarranged or incomplete state of works is for a watch;
and that seeing the general tendency of nature to this completeness
or state of comfort, we naturally conclude that the imaginations in
question, whether substantial or not, are at least not of the same
lasting or prevailing description.
We do not
profess metaphysics. We are indeed so little conversant with the
masters of that art, that we are never sure whether we are using even
its proper terms. All that we may know on the subject comes to us
from some reflection and some experience; and this all may be so
little as to make a metaphysician smile; which, if he be a true one,
he will do good-naturedly. The pretender will take occasion, from our
very confession, to say that we know nothing. Our faculty, such as it
is, is rather instinctive than reasoning; rather physical than
metaphysical; rather sentient because it loves much, than because it
knows much; rather calculated by a certain retention of boyhood, and
by its wanderings in the green places of thought, to light upon a
piece of the old golden world, than to tire ourselves, and conclude
it unattainable, by too wide and scientific a search. We pretend to
see farther than none but the worldly and the malignant. And yet
those who see farther may not see so well. We do not blind our eyes
with looking upon the sun in the heavens. We believe it to be there,
but we find its light upon earth also; and we would lead humanity, if
we could, out of misery and coldness into the shine of it. Pain might
still be there; must be so, as long as we are mortal;
“For oft we still
must weep, since we are human:”
but it should be pain
for the sake of others, which is noble; not unnecessary pain
inflicted by or upon them, which it is absurd not to remove. The very
pains of mankind struggle towards pleasures; and such pains as are
proper for them have this inevitable accompaniment of true
humanity,—that they cannot but realise a certain gentleness of
enjoyment. Thus the true bearer of pain would come round to us; and
he would not grudge us a share of his burden, though in taking from
his trouble it might diminish his pride. Pride is but a bad pleasure
at the expense of others. The great object of humanity is to enrich
everybody. If it is a task destined not to succeed, it is a good one
from its very nature; and fulfils at least a glad destiny of its own.
To look upon it austerely is in reality the reverse of austerity. It
is only such an impatience of the want of pleasure as leads us to
grudge it in others; and this impatience itself, if the sufferer knew
how to use it, is but another impulse, in the general yearning,
towards an equal wealth of enjoyment.
But we
shall be getting into other discussions.—The ground-work of all
happiness is health. Take care of this ground; and the doleful
imaginations that come to warn us against its abuse will avoid it.
Take care of this ground, and let as many glad imaginations throng to
it as possible. Read the magical works of the poets, and they will
come. If you doubt their existence, ask yourself whether you feel
pleasure at the idea of them; whether you are moved into delicious
smiles, or tears as delicious. If you are, the result is the same to
you, whether they exist or not. It is not mere words to say that he
who goes through a rich man’s park, and sees things in it which
never bless the mental eyesight of the possessor, is richer than he.
He is richer. More results of pleasure come home to him. The ground
is actually more fertile to him: the place haunted with finer shapes.
He has more servants to come at his call, and administer to him with
full hands. Knowledge, sympathy, imagination, are all divining-rods,
with which he discovers treasure. Let a painter go through the
grounds, and he will see not only the general colours of green and
brown, but their combinations and contrasts, and the modes in which
they might again be combined and contrasted. He will also put figures
in the landscape if there are none there, flocks and herds, or a
solitary spectator, or Venus lying with her white body among the
violets and primroses. Let a musician go through, and he will hear
“differences discreet” in the notes of the birds and the lapsing
of the water-fall. He will fancy a serenade of wind instruments in
the open air at a lady’s window, with a voice rising through it; or
the horn of the hunter; or the musical cry of the hounds,
“Matched
in mouth like bells,
Each under each;”
or a solitary voice in
a bower, singing for an expected lover; or the chapel organ, waking
up like the fountain of the winds. Let a poet go through the grounds
and he will heighten and increase all these sounds and images. He
will bring the colours from heaven, and put an unearthly meaning into
the voice. He will have stories of the sylvan inhabitants; will shift
the population through infinite varieties; will put a sentiment upon
every sight and sound; will be human, romantic, supernatural; will
make all nature send tribute into that spot.
We may say
of the love of nature what Shakespeare says of another love, that it
“Adds a precious
seeing to the eye.”
And we may say also,
upon the like principle, that it adds a precious hearing to the ear.
This and imagination, which ever follows upon it, are the two
purifiers of our sense, which rescue us from the deafening babble of
common cares, and enable us to hear all the affectionate voices of
earth and heaven. The starry orbs, lapsing about in their smooth and
sparkling dance, sing to us. The brooks talk to us of solitude. The
birds are the animal spirits of nature, carolling in the air, like a
careless lass.
“The
gentle gales,
Fanning their
odoriferous wings, dispense
Native perfumes; and
whisper whence they stole
Those balmy
spoils.”—Paradise Lost, book iv.
The poets are called
creators, because with their magical words they bring forth to our
eyesight the abundant images and beauties of creation. They put them
there, if the reader pleases; and so are literally creators. But
whether put there or discovered, whether created or invented (for
invention means nothing but finding out), there they are. If they
touch us, they exist to as much purpose as anything else which
touches us. If a passage in King Learbrings the tears
into our eyes, it is real as the touch of a sorrowful hand. If the
flow of a song of Anacreon’s intoxicates us, it is as true to a
pulse within us as the wine he drank. We hear not their sounds with
ears, nor see their sights with eyes; but we hear and see both so
truly, that we are moved with pleasure; and the advantage, nay even
the test, of seeing and hearing, at any time, is not in the seeing
and hearing, but in the ideas we realise, and the pleasure we derive.
Intellectual objects, therefore, inasmuch as they come home to us,
are as true a part of the stock of nature as visible ones; and they
are infinitely more abundant. Between the tree of a country clown and
the tree of a Milton on Spenser, what a difference in point of
productiveness! Between the plodding of a sexton through a churchyard
and the walk of a Gray, what a difference! What a difference between
the Bermudas of a ship-builder and the Bermoothes of Shakespeare! the
isle
“Full
of noises,
Sounds, and sweet airs,
that give delight, and hurt not;”
the isle of elves and
fairies, that chased the tide to and fro on the sea-shore; of
coral-bones and the knell of sea-nymphs; of spirits dancing on the
sands, and singing amidst the hushes of the wind; of Caliban, whose
brute nature enchantment had made poetical; of Ariel, who lay in
cowslip bells, and rode upon the bat; of Miranda who wept when she
saw Ferdinand work so hard, and begged him, to let her help; telling
him,
“I am your wife, if
you will marry me;
If not, I’ll die your
maid. To be your fellow
You may deny me; but
I’ll be your servant,
Whether you will or
no.”
Such are the
discoveries which the poets make for us; worlds to which that of
Columbus was but a handful of brute matter. America began to be
richer for us the other day, when Humboldt came back and told us of
its luxuriant and gigantic vegetation; of the myriads of shooting
lights, which revel at evening in the southern sky; and that grand
constellation, at which Dante seems to have made so remarkable a
guess (Purgatorio, cant. i., v. 22). The natural warmth
of the Mexican and Peruvian genius, set free from despotism, will
soon do all the rest for it; awaken the sleeping riches of its
eyesight, and call forth the glad music of its affections.
Imagination
enriches everything. A great library contains not only books, but
“The assembled souls
of all that men held wise.”
—DAVENANT.
The moon is Homer’s
and Shakespeare’s moon, as well as the one we look at. The sun
comes out of his chamber in the east, with a sparkling eye,
“rejoicing like a bridegroom.” The commonest thing becomes like
Aaron’s rod, that budded. Pope called up the spirits of the Cabala
to wait upon a lock of hair, and justly gave it the honours of a
constellation; for he has hung it, sparkling for ever in the eyes of
posterity. A common meadow is a sorry thing to a ditcher or a
coxcomb; but by the help of its dues from imagination and the love of
nature, the grass brightens for us, the air soothes us, we feel as we
did in the daisied hours of childhood. Its verdures, its sheep, its
hedge-row elms,—all these, and all else which sight, and sound, and
associations can give it, are made to furnish a treasure of pleasant
thoughts. Even brick and mortar are vivified, as of old, at the harp
of Orpheus. A metropolis becomes no longer a mere collection of
houses or of trades. It puts on all the grandeur of its history, and
its literature; its towers, and rivers; its art, and jewellery, and
foreign wealth; its multitude of human beings all intent upon
excitement, wise or yet to learn; the huge and sullen dignity of its
canopy of smoke by day; the wide gleam upwards of its lighted lustre
at nighttime; and the noise of its many chariots, heard at the same
hour, when the wind sets gently towards some quiet suburb.
0 comments