Fielding's Parody Becomes History
October 08, 2014Henry Fielding |
Henry Fielding (1742).
Preface to Joseph Andrews.
Vol. 39, pp. 176-181 of
The Harvard Classics
Fielding wrote a
lengthy story to burlesque a novel of Richardson. But the travesty
overshot its mark. Instead of a mere parody, it became a masterpiece.
(Henry Fielding died
Oct. 8, 1764.)
THE
COMIC EPIC IN PROSE
1 AS
IT is possible the mere English reader may have a
different idea of romance with the author of these little volumes;
and may consequently expect a kind of entertainment, not to be found,
nor which was even intended, in the following pages; it may not be
improper to premise a few words concerning this kind of writing,
which I do not remember to have seen hitherto attempted in our
language.
The EPIC,
as well as the DRAMA, is divided into tragedy and comedy. HOMER, who
was the father of this species of poetry, gave us the pattern of both
these, tho’ that of the latter kind is entirely lost; which
Aristotle tells us, bore the same relation to comedy which his Iliad
bears to tragedy. and perhaps, that we have no more instances of it
among the writers of antiquity, is owing to the loss of this great
pattern, which, had it survived, would have found its imitators
equally with the other poems of this great original.
And
farther, as this poetry may be tragic or comic, I will not scruple to
say it may be likewise either in verse or prose: for tho’ it wants
one particular, which the critic enumerates in the constituent parts
of an epic poem, namely, metre; yet, when any kind of writing
contains all its other parts, such as fable, action, characters,
sentiments, and diction, and is deficient in metre only, it seems, I
think, reasonable to refer it to the epic; at least, as no critic
hath thought proper to range it under any other head, nor to assign
it a particular name to itself.
Thus the
Telemachus of the archbishop of Cambray appears to me of the epic
kind, as well as the Odyssey of Homer; indeed, it is much fairer and
more reasonable to give it a name common with that species from which
it differs only in a single instance, than to confound it with those
which it resembles in no other. Such are those voluminous works,
commonly called Romances, namely Clelia, Cleopatra, Astræa,
Cassandra, the Grand Cyrus, and innumerable others which contain, as
I apprehend, very little instruction or entertainment.
Now, a
comic romance is a comic epic-poem in prose; differing from comedy,
as the serious epic from tragedy: its action being more extended and
comprehensive; containing a much larger circle of incidents, and
introducing a greater variety of characters. It differs from the
serious romance in its fable and action, in this: that as in the one
these are grave and solemn, so in the other they are light and
ridiculous; it differs in its characters, by introducing persons of
inferiour rank, and consequently of inferiour manners, whereas the
grave romance sets the highest before us; lastly in its sentiments
and diction; by preserving the ludicrous instead of the sublime. In
the diction I think, burlesque itself may be sometimes admitted; of
which many instances will occur in this work, as in the description
of the battles, and some other places not necessary to be pointed out
to the classical reader; for whose entertainment those parodies or
burlesque imitations are chiefly calculated.
But tho’
we have sometimes admitted this in our diction, we have carefully
excluded it from our sentiments and characters; for there it is never
properly introduced, unless in writings of the burlesque kind, which
this is not intended to be. Indeed, no two species of writing can
differ more widely than the comic and the burlesque: for as the
latter is ever the exhibition of what is monstrous and unnatural, and
where our delight, if we examine it, arises from the surprising
absurdity, as in appropriating the manners of the highest to the
lowest, or è converso; so in the former, we should
ever confine ourselves strictly to nature, from the just imitation of
which, will flow all the pleasure we can this way convey to a
sensible reader. and perhaps, there is one reason, why a comic writer
should of all others be the least excused for deviating from nature,
since it may not be always so easy for a serious poet to meet with
the great and the admirable; but life everywhere furnishes an
accurate observer with the ridiculous.
I have
hinted this little, concerning burlesque; because I have often heard
that name given to performances, which have been truly of the comic
kind, from the author’s having sometimes admitted it in his diction
only; which as it is the dress of poetry, doth like the dress of men
establish characters, (the one of the whole poem, and the other of
the whole man), in vulgar opinion, beyond any of their greater
excellences: but surely, a certain drollery in style, where
characters and sentiments are perfectly natural, no more constitutes
the burlesque, than an empty pomp and dignity of words, where
everything else is mean and low, can entitle any performance to the
appellation of the true sublime.
And I
apprehend, my Lord Shaftesbury’s opinion of mere burlesque agrees
with mine, when he asserts, “There is no such thing to be found in
the writings of the antients.” But perhaps I have less abhorrence
than he professes for it: and that not because I have had some little
success on the stage this way; but rather as it contributes more to
exquisite mirth and laughter than any other; and these are probably
more wholesome physic for the mind, and conduce better to purge away
spleen, melancholy, and ill affections, than is generally imagined.
Nay, I will appeal to common observation, whether the same companies
are not found more full of good-humour and benevolence, after they
have been sweetened for two or three hours with entertainments of
this kind, than soured by a tragedy or a grave lecture.
But to
illustrate all this by another science, in which, perhaps, we shall
see the distinction more clearly and plainly: let us examine the
works of a comic history-painter, with those performances which the
Italians call Caricatura, where we shall find the
greatest excellence of the former to consist in the exactest copy of
nature; insomuch, that a judicious eye instantly rejects
anything outré; any liberty which the painter hath
taken with the features of that alma mater. Whereas
in the Caricatura we allow all licence. Its aim is
to exhibit monsters, not men; and all distortions and exaggerations
whatever are within its proper province.
Now what
Caricatura is in painting, Burlesque is in writing; and in the same
manner the comic writer and painter correlate to each other. and here
I shall observe, that as in the former, the painter seems to have the
advantage; so it is in the latter infinitely on the side of the
writer: for the Monstrous is much easier to paint than describe, and
the Ridiculous to describe than paint.
And tho’
perhaps this latter species doth not in either science so strongly
affect and agitate the muscles as the other; yet it will be owned, I
believe, that a more rational and useful pleasure arises to us from
it. He who should call the ingenious Hogarth a burlesque painter,
would, in my opinion, do him very little honour: for sure it is much
easier, much less the subject of admiration, to paint a man with a
nose, or any other feature of a preposterous size, or to expose him
in some absurd or monstrous attitude, than to express the affections
of men on canvas. It hath been thought a vast commendation of a
painter to say his figures seem to breathe; but surely it
is a much greater and nobler applause, that they appear to
think.
But to
return. The Ridiculous only, as I have before said, falls within my
province in the present work. Nor will some explanation of this word
be thought impertinent by the reader, if he considers how wonderfully
it hath been mistaken, even by writers who have profess’d it: for
to what but such a mistake, can we attribute the many attempts to
ridicule the blackest villainies; and what is yet worse, the most
dreadful calamities? What could exceed the absurdity of an author,
who should write the comedy of Nero, with the merry incident of
ripping up his mother’s belly; or what would give a greater shock
to humanity than an attempt to expose the miseries of poverty and
distress to ridicule? and yet, the reader will not want much learning
to suggest such instances to himself.
Besides, it
may seem remarkable, that Aristotle, who is so fond and free of
definitions, hath not thought proper to define the Ridiculous.
Indeed, where he tells us it is proper to comedy, he hath remarked
that villainy is not its object: but that he hath not, as I remember,
positively asserted what is. Nor doth the Abbé Bellegarde, who hath
written a treatise on this subject, tho’ he shows us many species
of it, once trace it to its fountain.
The only
source of the true Ridiculous (as it appears to me) is affectation.
But tho’ it arises from one spring only, when we consider the
infinite streams into which this one branches, we shall presently
cease to admire at the copious field it affords to an observer. Now
affectation proceeds from one of these two causes; vanity, or
hypocrisy: for as vanity puts us on affecting false characters, in
order to purchase applause; so hypocrisy sets us on an endeavour to
avoid censure by concealing our vices under an appearance of their
opposite virtues. and tho’ these two causes are often confounded,
(for they require some distinguishing;) yet, as they proceed from
very different motives, so they are as clearly distinct in their
operations: for indeed, the affectation which arises from vanity is
nearer to truth than the other; as it hath not that violent
repugnancy of nature to struggle with, which that of the hypocrite
hath. It may be likewise noted, that affectation doth not imply an
absolute negation of those qualities which are affected: and
therefore, tho’, when it proceeds from hypocrisy, it be nearly
allied to deceit; yet when it comes from vanity only, it partakes of
the nature of ostentation: for instance, the affectation of
liberality in a vain man, differs visibly from the same affectation
in the avaricious; for tho’ the vain man is not what he would
appear, or hath not the virtue he affects, to the degree he would be
thought to have it; yet it sits less awkwardly on him than on the
avaricious man, who is the very reverse of what he would seem to be.
From the
discovery of this affectation arises the Ridiculous—which always
strikes the reader with surprize and pleasure; and that in a higher
and stronger degree when the affectation arises from hypocrisy, than
when from vanity: for to discover any one to be the exact reverse of
what he affects, is more surprizing, and consequently more
ridiculous, than to find him a little deficient in the quality he
desires the reputation of. I might observe that our Ben Jonson, who
of all men understood the Ridiculous the best, hath chiefly used the
hypocritical affectation.
Now from
affectation only, the misfortunes and calamities of life, or the
imperfections of nature, may become the objects of ridicule. Surely
he hath a very ill-framed mind, who can look on ugliness, infirmity,
or poverty, as ridiculous in themselves: nor do I believe any man
living who meets a dirty fellow riding through the streets in a cart,
is struck with an idea of the Ridiculous from it; but if he should
see the same figure descend from his coach and six, or bolt from his
chair with his hat under his arm, he would then begin to laugh, and
with justice. In the same manner, were we to enter a poor house and
behold a wretched family shivering with cold and languishing with
hunger, it would not incline us to laughter, (at least we must have
very diabolical natures, if it would): but should we discover there a
grate, instead of coals, adorned with flowers, empty plate or china
dishes on the side-board, or any other affectation of riches and
finery either on their persons or in their furniture; we might then
indeed be excused, for ridiculing so fantastical an appearance. Much
less are natural imperfections the object of derision: but when
ugliness aims at the applause of beauty, or lameness endeavours to
display agility; it is then that these unfortunate circumstances,
which at first moved our compassion, tend only to raise our mirth.
The poet
carries this very far;
None are for being what
they are in fault,
But for not being what
they would be thought.
Where if the metre
would suffer the word Ridiculous to close the first line, the thought
would be rather more proper. Great vices are the proper objects of
our detestation, smaller faults of our pity: but affectation appears
to me the only true source of the Ridiculous.
But perhaps
it may be objected to me, that I have against my own rules introduced
vices, and of a very black kind into this work. to this I shall
answer: First, that it is very difficult to pursue a series of human
actions and keep clear from them. Secondly, that the vices to be
found here, are rather the accidental consequences of some human
frailty, or foible, than causes habitually existing in the mind.
Thirdly, that they are never set forth as the objects of ridicule,
but detestation. Fourthly, that they are never the principal figure
at that time on the scene; lastly, they never produce the intended
evil.
Note
1. Henry Fielding, dramatist, novelist, and judge, was born near
Glastonbury, Somersetshire, April 22, 1707, and died at Lisbon,
October 8, 1754. Though seldom spoken of as an essayist, Fielding
scattered through his novels a large number of detached or detachable
discussions which are essentially essays, of which the preface to
“Joseph Andrews,” on the “Comic Epic in Prose,” is a
favorable specimen. The novel which it introduces was begun as a
parody on Richardson’s “Pamela,” and the preface gives
Fielding’s conception of this form of fiction.
0 comments