A Champion of Science
May 04, 2020Thomas Henry Huxley |
Thomas Henry Huxley.
Science and Culture
Vol. 28, pp. 209-219 of
The Harvard Classics
When science was
struggling for a place in popular education, Huxley distinguished
himself as its champion. While the arts were to beautify life and
increase pleasure, Huxley saw science as a means of benefiting man's
prosperity.
(Huxley born May 4,
1825.)
SIX 1 years
ago, as some of my present hearers may remember, I had the privilege
of addressing a large assemblage of the inhabitants of this city, who
had gathered together to do honor to the memory of their famous
townsman, Joseph Priestley; and, if any satisfaction attaches to
posthumous glory, we may hope that the manes of the burnt-out
philosopher were then finally appeased.
No man, however, who is endowed with a
fair share of common sense, and not more than a fair share of vanity,
will identify either contemporary or posthumous fame with the highest
good; and Priestley’s life leaves no doubt that he, at any rate,
set a much higher value upon the advancement of knowledge, and the
promotion of that freedom of thought which is at once the cause and
the consequence of intellectual progress.
Hence I am disposed to think that, if
Priestley could be amongst us to-day, the occasion of our meeting
would afford him even greater pleasure than the proceedings which
celebrated the centenary of his chief discovery. The kindly heart
would moved, the high sense of social duty would be satisfied, by the
spectacle of well-earned wealth, neither squandered in tawdry luxury
and vainglorious show, nor scattered with the careless charity which
blesses neither him that gives nor him that takes, but expended in
the execution of a well-considered plan for the aid of present and
future generations of those who are willing to help themselves.
We shall all be of one mind thus far.
But it is needful to share Priestley’s keen interest in physical
science; and to have learned, as he had learned, the value of
scientific training in fields of inquiry apparently far remote from
physical science; in order to appreciate, as he would have
appreciated, the value of the noble gift which Sir Josiah Mason has
bestowed upon the inhabitants of the Midland district.
For us children of the nineteenth
century, however, the establishment of a college under the conditions
of Sir Josiah Mason’s trust has a significance apart from any which
it could have possessed a hundred years ago. It appears to be an
indication that we are reaching the crisis of the battle, or rather
of the long series of battles, which have been fought over education
in a campaign which began long before Priestley’s time, and will
probably not be finished just yet.
In the last
century, the combatants were the champions of ancient literature, on
the one side, and those of modern literature on the other, but, some
thirty years 2 ago, the contest became
complicated by the appearance of a third army, ranged round the
banner of physical science.
I am not aware that any one has
authority to speak in the name of this new host. For it must be
admitted to be somewhat of a guerilla force, composed largely of
irregulars, each of whom fights pretty much for his own hand. But the
impressions of a full private, who has seen a good deal of service in
the ranks, respecting the present position of affairs and the
conditions of a permanent peace, may not be devoid of interest; and I
do not know that I could make a better use of the present opportunity
than by laying them before you.
From the time that the first
suggestion to introduce physical science into ordinary education was
timidly whispered, until now, the advocates of scientific education
have met with opposition of two kinds. On the one hand, they have
been poohpoohed by the men of business who pride themselves on being
the representatives of practicality; while, on the other hand, they
have been excommunicated by the classical scholars, in their capacity
of Levites in charge of the ark of culture and monopolists of liberal
education.
The practical men believed that the
idol whom they worship—rule of thumb—has been the source of the
past prosperity, and will suffice for the future welfare of the arts
and manufactures. They were of opinion that science is speculative
rubbish; that theory and practice have nothing to do with one
another; and that the scientific habit of mind is an impediment,
rather than an aid, in the conduct of ordinary affairs.
I have used the past tense in speaking
of the practical men—for although they were very formidable thirty
years ago, I am not sure that the pure species has not been
extirpated. In fact, so far as mere argument goes, they have been
subjected to such a feu d’enfer that it is a
miracle if any have escaped. But I have remarked that your typical
practical man has an unexpected resemblance to one of Milton’s
angels. His spiritual wounds, such as are inflicted by logical
weapons, may be as deep as a well and as wide as a church door, but
beyond shedding a few drops of ichor, celestial or otherwise, he is
no whit the worse. So, if any of these opponents be left, I will not
waste time in vain repetition of the demonstrative evidence of the
practical value of science; but knowing that a parable will sometimes
penetrate where syllogisms fail to effect an entrance, I will offer a
story for their consideration.
Once upon a time, a boy, with nothing
to depend upon but his own vigorous nature, was thrown into the thick
of the struggle for existence in the midst of a great manufacturing
population. He seems to have had a hard fight, inasmuch as, by the
time he was thirty years of age, his total disposable funds amounted
to twenty pounds. Nevertheless, middle life found him giving proof of
his comprehension of the practical problems he had been roughly
called upon to solve, by a career of remarkable prosperity.
Finally, having reached old age with
its well-earned surroundings of “honor, troops of friends,” the
hero of my story bethought himself of those who were making a like
start in life, and how he could stretch out a helping hand to them.
After long and anxious reflection this
successful practical man of business could devise nothing better than
to provide them with the means of obtaining “sound, extensive, and
practical scientific knowledge.” And he devoted a large part of his
wealth and five years of incessant work to this end.
I need not point the moral of a tale
which, as the solid and spacious fabric of the Scientific College
assures us, is no fable, nor can anything which I could say intensify
the force of this practical answer to practical objections.
We may take it for granted then, that,
in the opinion of those best qualified to judge, the diffusion of
thorough scientific education is an absolutely essential condition of
industrial progress; and that the college which has been opened
to-day will confer an inestimable boon upon those whose livelihood is
to be gained by the practice of the arts and manufactures of the
district.
The only question worth discussion is,
whether the conditions, under which the work of the college is to be
carried out, are such as to give it the best possible chance of
achieving permanent success.
Sir Josiah Mason, without doubt most
wisely, has left very large freedom of action to the trustees, to
whom he proposes ultimately to commit the administration of the
college, so that they may be able to adjust its arrangements in
accordance with the changing conditions of the future. But, with
respect to three points, he has laid most explicit injunctions upon
both administrators and teachers.
Party politics are forbidden to enter
into the minds of either, so far as the work of the college is
concerned; theology is as sternly banished from its precincts; and
finally, it is especially declared that the college shall make no
provision for “mere literary instruction and education.”
It does not concern me at present to
dwell upon the first two injunctions any longer than may be needful
to express my full conviction of their wisdom. But the third
prohibition brings us face to face with those other opponents of
scientific education, who are by no means in the moribund condition
of the practical man, but alive, alert, and formidable.
It is not impossible that we shall
hear this express exclusion of “literary instruction and education”
from a college which, nevertheless, professes to give a high and
efficient education, sharply criticised. Certainly the time was that
the Levites of culture would have sounded their trumpets against its
walls as against an educational Jericho.
How often have we not been told that
the study of physical science is incompetent to confer culture; that
it touches none of the higher problems of life; and, what is worse,
that the continual devotion to scientific studies tends to generate a
narrow and bigoted belief in the applicability of scientific methods
to the search after truth of all kinds. How frequently one has reason
to observe that no reply to a troublesome argument tells so well as
calling its author a “mere scientific specialist.” And, as I am
afraid it is not permissible to speak of this form of opposition to
scientific education in the past tense; may we not expect to be told
that this, not only omission, but prohibition, of “mere literary
instruction and education” is a patent example of scientific
narrow-mindedness?
I am not acquainted with Sir Josiah
Mason’s reasons for the action which he has taken; but if, as I
apprehend is the case, he refers to the ordinary classical course of
our schools and universities by the name of “mere literary
instruction and education,” I venture to offer sundry reasons of my
own in support of that action.
For I hold very strongly by two
convictions. The first is, that neither the discipline nor the
subject-matter of classical education is of such direct value to the
student of physical science as to justify the expenditure of valuable
time upon either; and the second is, that for the purpose of
attaining real culture, an exclusively scientific education is at
least as effectual as an exclusively literary education.
I need hardly point out to you that
these opinions, especially the latter, are diametrically opposed to
those of the great majority of educated Englishmen, influenced as
they are by school and university traditions. In their belief,
culture is obtainable only by a liberal education; and a liberal
education is synonymous, not merely with education and instruction in
literature, but in one particular form of literature, namely, that of
Greek and Roman antiquity. They hold that the man who has learned
Latin and Greek, however little, is educated; while he who is versed
in other branches of knowledge, however deeply, is a more or less
respectable specialist, not admissible into cultured caste. The stamp
of the educated man, the university degree, is not for him.
I am too well acquainted with the
generous catholicity of spirit, the true sympathy with scientific
thought, which pervades the writings of our chief apostle of culture
to identify him with these opinions; and yet one may cull from one
and another of those epistles to the Philistines, which so much
delight all who do not answer to that name, sentences which lend them
some support.
Mr. Arnold tells us that the meaning
of culture is “to know the best that has been thought and said in
the world.” It is the criticism of life contained in literature.
That criticism regards “Europe as being, for intellectual and
spiritual purposes, one great confederation, bound to a joint action
and working to a common result; and whose members have, for their
common outfit, a knowledge of Greek, Roman, and Eastern antiquity,
and of one another. Special, local, and temporary advantages being
put out of account, that modern nation will in the intellectual and
spiritual sphere make most progress, which most thoroughly carries
out this programme. And what is that but saying that we too, all of
us, as individuals, the more thoroughly we carry it out, shall make
the more progress?”
We have here to deal with two distinct
propositions. The first, that a criticism of life is the essence of
culture; the second, that literature contains the materials which
suffice for the construction of such a criticism.
I think that we must all assent to the
first proposition. For culture certainly means something quite
different from learning or technical skill. It implies the possession
of an ideal, and the habit of critically estimating the value of
things by comparison with a theoretic standard. Perfect culture
should apply a complete theory of life, based upon a clear knowledge
alike of its possibilities and of its limitations.
But we may agree to all this, and yet
strongly dissent from the assumption that literature alone is
competent to supply this knowledge. After having learnt all that
Greek, Roman, and Eastern antiquity have thought and said, and all
that modern literatures have to tell us, it is not self-evident that
we have laid a sufficiently broad and deep foundation for the
criticism of life which constitutes culture.
Indeed, to any one acquainted with the
scope of physical science, it is not at all evident. Considering
progress only in the “intellectual and spiritual sphere,” I find
myself wholly unable to admit that either nations or individuals will
really advance, if their common outfit draws nothing from the stores
of physical science. I should say that an army, without weapons of
precision, and with no particular base of operations, might more
hopefully enter upon a campaign on the Rhine, than a man, devoid of a
knowledge of what physical science has done in the last century, upon
a criticism of life.
When a biologist meets with an
anomaly, he instinctively turns to the study of development to clear
it up. The rationale of contradictory opinions may with equal
confidence be sought in history.
It is, happily, no new thing that
Englishmen should employ their wealth in building and endowing
institutions for educational purposes. But, five or six hundred years
ago, deeds of foundation expressed or implied conditions as nearly as
possible contrary to those which have been thought expedient by Sir
Josiah Mason. That is to say, physical science was practically
ignored, while a certain literary training was enjoined as a means to
the acquirement of knowledge which was essentially theological.
The reason of this singular
contradiction between the actions of men alike animated by a strong
and disinterested desire to promote the welfare of their fellows, is
easily discovered.
At that time, in fact, if any one
desired knowledge beyond such as could be obtained by his own
observation, or by common conversation, his first necessity was to
learn the Latin language, inasmuch as all the higher knowledge of the
western world was contained in works written in that language. Hence,
Latin grammar, with logic and rhetoric, studied through Latin, were
the fundamentals of education. With respect to the substance of the
knowledge imparted through this channel, the Jewish and Christian
Scriptures, as interpreted and supplemented by the Romish Church,
were held to contain a complete and infallibly true body of
information.
Theological dicta were, to the
thinkers of those days, that which the axioms and definitions of
Euclid are to the geometers of these. The business of the
philosophers of the Middle Ages was to deduce from the data furnished
by the theologians, conclusions in accordance with ecclesiastical
decrees. They were allowed the high privilege of showing, by logical
process, how and why that which the Church said was true, must be
true. And if their demonstrations fell short of or exceeded this
limit, the Church was maternally ready to check their aberrations, if
need be, by the help of the secular arm.
Between the two, our ancestors were
furnished with a compact and complete criticism of life. They were
told how the world began, and how it would end; they learned that all
material existence was but a base and insignificant blot upon the
fair face of the spiritual world, and that nature was, to all intents
and purposes, the playground of the devil; they learned that the
earth is the centre of the visible universe, and that man is the
cynosure of things terrestrial; and more especially is it inculcated
that the course of nature had no fixed order, but that it could be,
and constantly was, altered by the agency of innumerable spiritual
beings, good and bad, according as they were moved by the deeds and
prayers of men. The sum and substance of the whole doctrine was to
produce the conviction that the only thing really worth knowing in
this world was how to secure that place in a better, which, under
certain conditions, the Church promised.
Our ancestors had a living belief in
this theory of life, and acted upon it in their dealings with
education, as in all other matters. Culture meant saintliness—after
the fashion of the saints of those days; the education that led to it
was, of necessity, theological; and the way to theology lay through
Latin.
That the study of nature—further
than was requisite for the satisfaction of everyday wants—should
have any bearing on human life was far from the thoughts of men thus
trained. Indeed, as nature had been cursed for man’s sake, it was
an obvious conclusion that those who meddled with nature were likely
to come into pretty close contact with Satan. And, if any born
scientific investigator followed his instincts, he might safely
reckon upon earning the reputation, and probably upon suffering the
fate, of a sorcerer.
Had the western world been left to
itself in Chinese isolation, there is no saying how long this state
of things might have endured. But, happily, it was not left to
itself. Even earlier than the thirteenth century, the development of
Moorish civilization in Spain and the great movement of the Crusades
had introduced the leaven which, from that day to this, has never
ceased to work. At first, through the intermediation of Arabic
translations, afterwards by the study of the originals, the western
nations of Europe became acquainted with the writings of the ancient
philosophers and poets, and, in time, with the whole of the vast
literature of antiquity.
Whatever there was of high
intellectual aspiration or dominant capacity in Italy, France,
Germany, and England, spent itself for centuries in taking possession
of the rich inheritance left by the dead civilization of Greece and
Rome. Marvelously aided by the invention of printing, classical
learning spread and flourished. Those who possessed it prided
themselves on having attained the highest culture then within the
reach of mankind.
And justly. For, saving Dante on his
solitary pinnacle, there was no figure in modern literature at the
time of the Renaissance to compare with the men of antiquity; there
was no art to compete with their sculpture; there was no physical
science but that which Greece had created. Above all, there was no
other example of perfect intellectual freedom—of the unhesitating
acceptance of reason as the sole guide to truth and the supreme
arbiter of conduct.
The new learning necessarily soon
exerted a profound influence upon education. The language of the
monks and schoolmen seemed little better than gibberish to scholars
fresh from Vergil and Cicero, and the study of Latin was placed upon
a new foundation. Moreover, Latin itself ceased to afford the sole
key to knowledge. The student who sought the highest thought of
antiquity found only a second-hand reflection of it in Roman
literature, and turned his face to the full light of the Greeks. And
after a battle, not altogether dissimilar to that which is at present
being fought over the teaching of physical science, the study of
Greek was recognized as an essential element of all higher education.
Thus the humanists, as they were
called, won the day; and the great reform which they effected was of
incalculable service to mankind. But the Nemesis of all reformers is
finality; and the reformers of education, like those of religion,
fell into the profound, however common, error of mistaking the
beginning for the end of the work of reformation.
The representatives of the humanists
in the nineteenth century take their stand upon classical education
as the sole avenue to culture, as firmly as if we were still in the
age of Renaissance. Yet, surely, the present intellectual relations
of the modern and the ancient worlds are profoundly different from
those which obtained three centuries ago. Leaving aside the existence
of a great and characteristically modern literature, of modern
painting, and, especially, of modern music, there is one feature of
the present state of the civilized world which separates it more
widely from the Renaissance than the Renaissance was separated from
the Middle Ages.
This distinctive character of our own
times lies in the vast and constantly increasing part which is played
by natural knowledge. Not only is our daily life shaped by it, not
only does the prosperity of millions of men depend upon it, but our
whole theory of life has long been influenced, consciously or
unconsciously, by the general conceptions of the universe, which have
been forced upon us by physical science.
In fact, the most elementary
acquaintance with the results of scientific investigation shows us
that they offer a broad and striking contradiction to the opinions so
implicitly credited and taught in the Middle Ages.
The notions of the beginning and the
end of the world entertained by our forefathers are no longer
credible. It is very certain that the earth is not the chief body in
the material universe, and that the world is not subordinated to
man’s use. It is even more certain that nature is the expression of
a definite order with which nothing interferes, and that the chief
business of mankind is to learn that order and govern themselves
accordingly. Moreover this scientific “criticism of life”
presents itself to us with different credentials from any other. It
appeals not to authority, nor to what anybody may have thought or
said, but to nature. It admits that all our interpretations of
natural fact are more or less imperfect and symbolic, and bids the
learner seek for truth not among words but among things. It warns us
that the assertion which outstrips evidence is not only a blunder but
a crime.
The purely classical education
advocated by the representatives of the humanists in our day gives no
inkling of all this. A man may be a better scholar than Erasmus, and
know no more of the chief causes of the present intellectual
fermentation than Erasmus did. Scholarly and pious persons, worthy of
all respect, favor us with allocutions upon the sadness of the
antagonism of science to their mediaeval way of thinking, which
betray an ignorance of the first principles of scientific
investigation, an incapacity for understanding what a man of science
means by veracity, and an unconsciousness of the weight of
established scientific truths, which is almost comical.
There is no great force in the tu
quoque argument, or else the advocates of scientific education might
fairly enough retort upon the modern humanists that they may be
learned specialists, but that they possess no such sound foundation
for a criticism of life as deserves the name of culture. And, indeed,
if we were disposed to be cruel, we might urge that the humanists
have brought this reproach upon themselves, not because they are too
full of the spirit of the ancient Greek, but because they lack it.
The period of the Renaissance is
commonly called that of the “Revival of Letters,” as if the
influences then brought to bear upon the mind of Western Europe had
been wholly exhausted in the field of literature. I think it is very
commonly forgotten that the revival of science, effected by the same
agency, although less conspicuous, was not less momentous.
In fact, the few and scattered
students of nature of that day picked up the clew to her secrets
exactly as it fell from the hands of the Greeks a thousand years
before. The foundations of mathematics were so well laid by them that
our children learn their geometry from a book written for the schools
of Alexandria two thousand years ago. Modern astronomy is the natural
continuation and development of the work of Hipparchus and of
Ptolemy; modern physics of that of Democritus and of Archimedes; it
was long before modern biological science outgrew the knowledge
bequeathed to us by Aristotle, by Theophrastus, and by Galen.
We cannot know all the best thoughts
and sayings of the Greeks unless we know what they thought about
natural phenomena. We cannot fully apprehend their criticism of life
unless we understand the extent to which that criticism was affected
by scientific conceptions. We falsely pretend to be the inheritors of
their culture, unless we are penetrated, as the best minds among them
were, with an unhesitating faith that the free employment of reason,
in accordance with scientific method, is the sole method of reaching
truth.
Note
1. Originally delivered as an address, in 1880, at the
opening of Mason College, Birmingham, England, now the University of
Birmingham.
Note 2. The
advocacy of the introduction of physical science into general
education by George Combe and others commenced a good deal earlier;
but the movement had acquired hardly any practical force before the
time to which I refer.
0 comments