Which Is a Beautiful Woman?
August 23, 2014Edmund Burke |
Edmund Burke
(1729–1797). On the Sublime and Beautiful.
Vol. 24, pp. 78-88 of
The Harvard Classics
The Hottentot thinks
his wife beautiful. Every American believes his wife also to be
beautiful. But the American and the Hottentot are quite different.
What, after all, is Beauty?
Proportion
not the Cause of Beauty in Animals
THAT proportion has but
a small share in the formation of beauty, is full as evident among
animals. Here the greatest variety of shapes and dispositions of
parts are well fitted to excite this idea. The swan, confessedly a
beautiful bird, has a neck longer than the rest of his body, and but
a very short tail: is this a beautiful proportion? We must allow that
it is. But then what shall we say to the peacock, who has
comparatively but a short neck, with a tail longer than the neck and
the rest of the body taken together? How many birds are there that
vary infinitely from each of these standards, and from every other
which you can fix; with proportions different, and often directly
opposite to each other! and yet many of these birds are extremely
beautiful; when upon considering them we find nothing in any one part
that might determine us, a priori, to say what the others ought to
be, nor indeed to guess anything about them, but what experience
might show to be full of disappointment and mistake. And with regard
to the colours either of birds or flowers, for there is something
similar in the colouring of both, whether they are considered in
their extension or gradation, there is nothing of proportion to be
observed.
Some are of but one single colour, others have all the
colours of the rainbow; some are of the primary colours, others are
of the mixt; in short, an attentive observer may soon conclude, that
there is as little of proportion in the colouring as in the shapes of
these objects. Turn next to beasts; examine the head of a beautiful
horse; find what proportion that bears to his body, and to his limbs,
and what relations these have to each other; and when you have
settled these proportions as a standard of beauty, then take a dog or
cat, or any other animal, and examine how far the same proportions
between their heads and their necks, between those and the body, and
so on, are found to hold. I think we may safely say, that they differ
in every species, yet that there are individuals, found in a great
many species so differing, that have a very striking beauty. Now, if
it be allowed that very different and even contrary forms and
dispositions are consistent with beauty, it amounts I believe to a
concession, that no certain measures, operating from a natural
principle, are necessary to produce it; at least so far as the brute
species is concerned.
Proportion
not the Cause of Beauty in the Human Species
THERE are some parts of
the human body that are observed to hold certain proportions to each
other; but before it can be proved that the efficient cause of beauty
lies in these, it must be shown, that wherever these are found exact;
the person to whom they belong is beautiful: I mean in the effect
produced on the view, either of any member distinctly considered, or
of the whole body together. It must be likewise shown, that these
parts stand in such a relation to each other, that the comparison
between them may be easily made, and that the affection of the mind
may naturally result from it. For my part, I have at several times
very carefully examined many of those proportions, and found them
hold very nearly or altogether alike in many subjects, which were not
only very different from one another, but where one has been very
beautiful, and the other very remote from beauty. With regard to the
parts which are found so proportioned, they are often so remote from
each other, in situation, nature, and office, that I cannot see how
they admit of any comparison, nor consequently how any effect owing
to proportion can result from them. The neck, say they, in beautiful
bodies, should measure with the calf of the leg; it should likewise
be twice the circumference of the wrist. And an infinity of
observations of this kind are to be found in the writings and
conversations of many. But what relation has the calf of the leg to
the neck; or either of these parts to the wrist? These proportions
are certainly to be found in handsome bodies. They are as certainly
in ugly ones; as any who will take the pains to try may find. Nay, I
do not know but they may be least perfect in some of the most
beautiful. You may assign any proportion you please to every part of
the human body; and I undertake that a painter shall religiously
observe them all, and notwithstanding produce, if he pleases, a very
ugly figure. The same painter shall considerably deviate from these
proportions, and produce a very beautiful one. And indeed it may be
observed in the master-pieces of the ancient and modern statuary,
that several of them differ very widely from the proportions of
others, in parts very conspicuous and of great consideration; and
that they differ no less from the proportions we find in living men,
of forms extremely striking and agreeable. And after all, how are the
partisans of proportional beauty agreed amongst themselves about the
proportions of the
human body? Some hold it to be seven heads; some make it eight;
whilst others extend it even to ten; a vast difference in such a
small number of divisions! Others take other methods of estimating
the proportions, and all with equal success. But are these
proportions exactly the same in all handsome men? or are they at all
the proportions found in beautiful women? Nobody will say that they
are; yet both sexes are undoubtedly capable of beauty, and the female
of the greatest; which advantage I believe will hardly be attributed
to the superior exactness of proportion in the fair sex. Let us rest
a moment on this point; and consider how much difference there is
between the measures that prevail in many similar parts of the body,
in the two sexes of this single species only. If you assign any
determinate proportions to the limbs of a man, and if you limit human
beauty to these proportions, when you find a woman who differs in the
make and measures of almost every part, you must conclude her not to
be beautiful, in spite of the suggestions of your imagination; or, in
obedience to your imagination, you must renounce your rules; you must
lay by the scale and compass, and look out for some other cause of
beauty. For if beauty be attached to certain measures which operate
from a principle in nature, why should similar parts with different
measures of proportion be found to have beauty, and this too in the
very same species? But to open our view a little, it is worth
observing, that almost all animals have parts of very much the same
nature, and destined nearly to the same purposes; a head, neck, body,
feet, eyes, ears, nose, and mouth; yet Providence to provide in the
best manner for their several wants, and to display the riches of his
wisdom and goodness in his creation, has worked out of these few and
similar organs and members, a diversity hardly short of infinite in
their disposition, measures, and relation. But, as we have before
observed, amidst this infinite diversity, one particular is common to
many species: several of the individuals which compose them are
capable of affecting us with a sense of loveliness; and whilst they
agree in producing this effect, they differ extremely in the relative
measures of those parts which have produced it. These considerations
were sufficient to induce me to reject the notion of any particular
proportions that operated by nature to produce a pleasing effect; but
those who will agree with me with regard to a particular proportion,
are strongly prepossessed in favour of one more indefinite. They
imagine, that although beauty in general is annexed to no certain
measures common to the several kinds of pleasing plants and animals;
yet that there is a certain proportion in each species absolutely
essential to the beauty of that particular kind. If we consider the
animal world in general, we find beauty confined to no certain
measures: but as some peculiar measure and relation of parts is what
distinguishes each peculiar class of animals, it must of necessity
be, that the beautiful in each kind will be found in the measures and
proportions of that kind; for otherwise it would deviate from its
proper species, and become in some sort monstrous: however, no
species is so strictly confined to any certain proportions, that
there is not a considerable variation amongst the individuals; and as
it has been shown of the human, so it may be shown of the brute
kinds, that beauty is found indifferently in all the proportions
which each kind can admit, without quitting its common form; and it
is this idea of a common form that makes the proportion of parts at
all regarded, and not the operation of any natural cause: indeed a
little consideration will make it appear, that it is not measure, but
manner, that creates all the beauty which belongs to shape. What
light do we borrow from these boasted proportions, when we study
ornamental design? It seems amazing to me, that artists, if they were
as well convinced as they pretend to be, that proportion is a
principal cause of beauty, have not by them at all times accurate
measurements of all sorts of beautiful animals to help them to proper
proportions, when they would contrive anything elegant; especially as
they frequently assert that it is from an observation of the
beautiful in nature they direct their practice. I know that it has
been said longasince, and echoed backward and forward from one writer
to another a thousand times, that the proportions of building have
been taken from those of the human body. To make this forced analogy
complete, they represent a man with his arms raised and extended at
full length, and then describe a sort of square, as it is formed by
passing lines along the extremities of this strange figure. But it
appears very clearly to me, that the human figure never supplied the
architect with any of his ideas. For, in the first place, men are
very rarely seen in this strained posture; it is not natural to them;
neither is it at all becoming. Secondly, the view of the human figure
so disposed, does not naturally suggest the idea of a square, but
rather of a cross; as that large space between the arms and the
ground must be filled with something before it can make anybody think
of a square. Thirdly, several buildings are by no means of the form
of that particular square, which are notwithstanding planned by the
best architects, and produce an effect altogether as good, and
perhaps a better. And certainly nothing could be more unaccountably
whimsical, than for an architect to model his performance by the
human figure, since no two things can have less resemblance or
analogy, than a man and a house, or temple: do we need to observe,
that their purposes are entirely different? What I am apt to suspect
is this: that these analogies were devised to give a credit to the
work of art, by showing a conformity between them and the noblest
works in nature; not that the latter served at all to supply hints
for the perfection of the former. And I am the more fully convinced,
that the patrons of proportion have transferred their artificial
ideas to nature, and not borrowed from thence the proportions they
use in works of art; because in any discussion of this subject they
always quit as soon as possible the open field of natural beauties,
the animal and vegetable kingdoms, and fortify themselves within the
artificial lines and angles of architecture. For there is in mankind
an unfortunate propensity to make themselves, their views, and their
works, the measure of excellence in everything whatsoever. Therefore,
having observed that their dwellings were most commodious and firm
when they were thrown into regular figures, with parts answerable to
each other; they transferred these ideas to their gardens; they
turned their trees into pillars, pyramids, and obelisks; they formed
their hedges into so many green walls, and fashioned their walks into
squares, triangles, and other mathematical figures, with exactness
and symmetry; and they thought, if they were not imitating, they were
at least improving nature, and teaching her to know her business. But
nature has at last escaped from their discipline and their fetters;
and our gardens, if nothing else, declare we begin to feel that
mathematical ideas are not the true measures of beauty. And surely
they are full as little so in the animal as the vegetable world. For
is it not extraordinary, that in these fine descriptive pieces, these
innumerable odes and elegies, which are in the mouths of all the
world, and many of which have been the entertainment of ages, that in
these pieces which describe love with such a passionate energy, and
represent its object in such an infinite variety of lights, not one
word is said of proportion, if it be, what some insist it is, the
principal component of beauty; whilst, at the same time, several
other qualities are very frequently and warmly mentioned? But if
proportion has not this power, it may appear odd how men came
originally to be so pre-possessed in its favour. It arose, I imagine,
from the fondness I have just mentioned, which men bear so remarkably
to their own works and notions; it arose from false reasonings on the
effects of the customary figure of animals; it arose from the
Platonic theory of fitness and aptitude. For which reason, in the
next section, I shall consider the effects of custom in the figure of
animals; and afterwards the idea of fitness: since, if proportion
does not operate by a natural power attending some measures, it must
be either by custom, or the idea of utility; there is no other way.
Proportion Further
Considered
IF I am not mistaken, a
great deal of the prejudice in favour of proportion has arisen, not
so much from the observation of any certain measures found in
beautiful bodies, as from a wrong idea of the relation which
deformity bears to beauty, to which it has been considered as the
opposite; on this principle it was concluded, that where the causes
of deformity were removed, beauty must naturally and necessarily be
introduced. This I believe is a mistake. For deformity is opposed not
to beauty, but to the complete common form. If one of the legs of a
man be found shorter than the other, the man is deformed; because
there is something wanting to complete the whole idea we form of a
man; and this has the same effect in natural faults, as maiming and
mutilation produce from accidents. So if the back be humped, the man
is deformed; because his back has an unusual figure, and what carries
with it the idea of some disease or misfortune. So if a man’s neck
be considerably longer or shorter than usual, we say he is deformed
in that part, because men are not commonly made in that manner. But
surely every hour’s experience may convince us, that a man may have
his legs of an equal length, and resembling each other in all
respects, and his neck of a just size, and his back quite straight,
without having at the same time the least perceivable beauty. Indeed
beauty is so far from belonging to the idea of custom, that in
reality what affects us in that manner is extremely rare and
uncommon. The beautiful strikes us as much by its novelty as the
deformed itself. It is thus in those species of animals with which we
are acquainted; and if one of a new species were represented, we
should by no means wait until custom had settled an idea of
proportion, before we decided concerning its beauty or ugliness:
which shows that the general idea of beauty can be no more owing to
customary than to natural proportion. Deformity arises from the want
of the common proportions; but the necessary result of their
existence in any object is not beauty. If we suppose proportion in
natural things to be relative to custom and use, the nature of use
and custom will show, that beauty, which is a positive and powerful
quality, cannot result from it. We are so wonderfully formed, that,
whilst we are creatures vehemently desirous of novelty, we are as
strongly attached to habit and custom. But it is the nature of things
which hold us by custom, to affect us very little whilst we are in
possession of them, but strongly when they are absent. I remember to
have frequented a certain place every day for a long time together;
and I may truly say, that so far from finding pleasure in it, I was
affected with a sort of weariness and disgust; I came, I went, I
returned, without pleasure; yet if by any means I passed by the usual
time of my going thither, I was remarkably uneasy, and was not quiet
till I had got into my old track. They who use snuff, take it almost
without being sensible that they take it, and the acute sense of
smell is deadened, so as to feel hardly anything from so sharp a
stimulus; yet deprive the snuff-taker of his box, and he is the most
uneasy mortal in the world. Indeed so far are use and habit from
being causes of pleasure, merely as such, that the effect of constant
use is to make all things of whatever kind entirely unaffecting. For
as use at last takes off the painful effect of many things, it
reduces the pleasurable effect in others in the same manner, and
brings both to a sort of mediocrity and indifference. Very justly is
use called a second nature; and our natural and common state is one
of absolute indifference, equally prepared for pain or pleasure. But
when we are thrown out of this state, or deprived of anything
requisite to maintain us in it; when this chance does not happen by
pleasure from some mechanical cause, we are always hurt. It is so
with the second nature, custom, in all things which relate to it.
Thus the want of the usual proportions in men and other animals is
sure to disgust, though their presence is by no means any cause of
real pleasure. It is true, that the proportions laid down as causes
of beauty in the human body, are frequently found in beautiful ones,
because they are generally found in all mankind; but if it can be
shown too, that they are found without beauty, and that beauty
frequently exists without them, and that this beauty, where it
exists, always can be assigned to other less equivocal causes, it
will naturally lead us to conclude, that proportion and beauty are
not ideas of the same nature. The true opposite to beauty is not
disproportion or deformity, but ugliness: and as it proceeds from
causes opposite to those of positive beauty, we cannot consider it
until we come to treat of that. Between beauty and ugliness there is
a sort of mediocrity, in which the assigned proportions are most
commonly found; but this has no effect upon the passions.
Fitness not the
Cause of Beauty
IT is said that the
idea of utility, or of a part’s being well adapted to answer its
end, is the cause of beauty, or indeed beauty itself. If it were not
for this opinion, it had been impossible for the doctrine of
proportion to have held its ground very long; the world would be soon
weary of hearing of measures which related to nothing, either of a
natural principle, or of a fitness to answer some end; the idea which
mankind most commonly conceive of proportion, is the suitableness of
means to certain ends, and, where this is not the question, very
seldom trouble themselves about the effect of different measures of
things. Therefore it was necessary for this theory to insist, that
not only artificial but natural objects took their beauty from the
fitness of the parts for their several purposes. But in framing this
theory, I am apprehensive that experience was not sufficiently
consulted. For, on that principle, the wedge-like snout of a swine,
with its tough cartilage at the end, the little sunk eyes, and the
whole make of the head, so well adapted to its offices of digging and
rooting, would be extremely beautiful. The great bag hanging to the
bill of a pelican, a thing highly useful to this animal, would be
likewise as beautiful in our eyes. The hedge-hog, so well secured
against all assaults by his prickly hide, and the porcupine with his
missile quills, would be then considered as creatures of no small
elegance. There are few animals whose parts are better contrived than
those of the monkey; he has the hands of a man, joined to the springy
limbs of a beast; he is admirably calculated for running, leaping,
grappling, and climbing; and yet there are few animals which seem to
have less beauty in the eyes of all mankind. I need say little on the
trunk of the elephant, of such various usefulness, and which is so
far from contributing to his beauty. How well fitted is the wolf for
running and leaping! how admirably is the lion armed for battle! but
will any one therefore call the elephant, the wolf, and the lion,
beautiful animals? I believe nobody will think the form of a man’s
leg so well adapted to running, as those of a horse, a dog, a deer,
and several other creatures; at least they have not that appearance:
yet, I believe, a well-fashioned human leg will be allowed to far
exceed all these in beauty. If the fitness of parts was what
constituted the loveliness of their form, the actual employment of
them would undoubtedly much augment it; but this, though it is
sometimes so upon another principle, is far from being always the
case. A bird on the wing is not so beautiful as when it is perched;
nay, there are several of the domestic fowls which are seldom seen to
fly, and which are nothing the less beautiful on that account; yet
birds are so extremely different in their form from the beast and
human kinds, that you cannot, on the principle of fitness, allow them
anything agreeable, but in consideration of their parts being
designed for quite other purposes. I never in my life chanced to see
a peacock fly; and yet before, very long before, I considered any
aptitude in his form for the aërial life, I was struck with the
extreme beauty which raises that bird above many of the best flying
fowls in the world; though, for anything I saw, his way of living was
much like that of the swine, which fed in the farm-yard along with
him. The same may be said of cocks, hens, and the like; they are of
the flying kind in figure; in their manner of moving not very
different from men and beasts. To leave these foreign examples; if
beauty in our own species was annexed to use, men would be much more
lovely than women; and strength and agility would be considered as
the only beauties. But to call strength by the name of beauty, to
have but one denomination for the qualities of a Venus and Hercules,
so totally different in almost all respects, is surely a strange
confusion of ideas, or abuse of words. The cause of this confusion, I
imagine, proceeds from our frequently perceiving the parts of the
human and other animal bodies to be at once very beautiful, and very
well adapted to their purposes; and we are deceived by a sophism,
which makes us take that for a cause which is only a concomitant:
this is the sophism of the fly, who imagined he raised a great dust,
because he stood upon the chariot that really raised it. The stomach,
the lungs, the liver, as well as other parts, are incomparably well
adapted to their purposes; yet they are far from having any beauty.
Again, many things are very beautiful, in which it is impossible to
discern any idea of use. And I appeal to the first and most natural
feelings of mankind, whether on beholding a beautiful eye, or a
well-fashioned mouth, or a well-turned leg, any ideas of their being
well fitted for seeing, eating, or running, ever present themselves.
What idea of use is it that flowers excite, the most beautiful part
of the vegetable world? It is true, that the infinitely wise and good
Creator has, of his bounty, frequently joined beauty to those things
which he has made useful to us: but this does not prove that an idea
of use and beauty are the same thing, or that they are any way
dependent on each other.
The
Real Effects of Fitness
WHEN I excluded
proportion and fitness from any share in beauty, I did not by any
means intend to say that they were of no value, or that they ought to
be disregarded in works of art. Works of art are the proper sphere of
their power; and here it is that they have their full effect.
Whenever the wisdom of our Creator intended that we should be
affected with anything, he did not confide the execution of his
design to the languid and precarious operation of our reason; but he
enduced it with powers and properties that prevent the understanding,
and even the will; which, seizing upon the senses and imagination,
captivate the soul before the understanding is ready either to join
with them, or to oppose them. It is by a long deduction, and much
study, that we discover the adorable wisdom of God in his works: when
we discover it, the effect is very different, not only in the manner
of acquiring it, but in its own nature, from that which strikes us
without any preparation from the sublime or the beautiful. How
different is the satisfaction of an anatomist, who discovers the use
of the muscles and of the skin, the excellent contrivance of the one
for the various movements of the body, and the wonderful texture of
the other, at once a general covering, and at once a general outlet
as well as inlet; how different is this from the affection which
possesses an ordinary man at the sight of a delicate, smooth skin,
and all the other parts of beauty, which require no investigation to
be perceived! In the former case, whilst we look up to the Maker with
admiration and praise, the object which causes it may be odious and
distasteful; the latter very often so touches us by its power on the
imagination, that we examine but little into the artifice of its
contrivance; and we have need of a strong effort of our reason to
disentangle our minds from the allurements of the object, to a
consideration of that wisdom which invented so powerful a machine.
The effect of proportion and fitness, at least so far as they proceed
from a mere consideration of the work itself, produces approbation,
the acquiescence of the understanding, but not love, nor any passion
of that species. When we examine the structure of a watch, when we
come to know thoroughly the use of every part of it, satisfied as we
are with the fitness of the whole, we are far enough from perceiving
anything like beauty in the watchwork itself; but let us look on the
case, the labour of some curious artist in engraving, with little or
no idea of use, we shall have a much livelier idea of beauty than we
ever could have had from the watch itself, though the master-piece of
Graham. In beauty, as I said, the effect is previous to any knowledge
of the use; but to judge of proportion, we must know the end for
which any work is designed. According to the end, the proportion
varies. Thus there is one proportion of a tower, another of a house;
one proportion of a gallery, another of a hall, another of a chamber.
To judge of the proportions of these, you must be first acquainted
with the purposes for which they were designed. Good sense and
experience, acting together, find out what is fit to be done in every
work of art. We are rational creatures, and in all our works we ought
to regard their end and purpose; the gratification of any passion,
how innocent soever, ought only to be of a secondary consideration.
Herein is placed the real power of fitness and proportion; they
operate on the understanding considering them, which approves the
work and acquiesces in it. The passions, and the imagination which
principally raises them, have here very little to do. When a room
appears in its original nakedness, bare walls and a plain ceiling;
let its proportion be ever so excellent, it pleases very little; a
cold approbation is the utmost we can reach; a much worse
proportioned room with elegant mouldings and fine festoons, glasses,
and other merely ornamental furniture, will make the imagination
revolt against the reason; it will please much more than the naked
proportion of the first room, which the understanding has so much
approved as admirably fitted for its purposes. What I have here said
and before concerning proportion, is by no means to persuade people
absurdly to neglect the idea of use in the works of art. It is only
to show that these excellent things, beauty and proportion, are not
the same; not that they should either of them be disregarded.
0 comments