Less Than Star Dust
November 23, 2014Blaise Pascal |
Blaise Pascal
(1623–1662). Thoughts.
Vol. 48, pp. 26-36 of
The Harvard Classics
According to Pascal,
a man is not even as significant as a speck of star dust in the
universe. Pascal's thoughts on the subject are startling to the
modern reader, and they furnish rich food for the imagination.
(Pascal begins
writing his "Thoughts," Nov. 23, 1654.)
Section
II
The
Misery Of Man Without God
[…]
68
Men are never taught to be gentlemen, and are taught everything else; and they never plume themselves so much on the rest of their knowledge as on knowing how to be gentlemen. They only plume themselves on knowing the one thing they do not know.
69
The infinites, the mean.—When we read too fast or too slowly, we understand nothing.
70
Nature…—[Nature has set us so well in the centre, that if we change one side of the balance, we change the other also. I act. [Greek]. 1 This makes me believe that the springs in our brain are so adjusted that he who touches one touches also its contrary.]
71
Too much and too little wine. Give him none, he cannot find truth; give him too much, the same.
72
Man’s disproportion.—[This is where our innate knowledge leads us. If it be not true, there is no truth in man; and if it be true, he finds therein great cause for humiliation, being compelled to abase himself in one way or another. And since he cannot exist without this knowledge, I wish that, before entering on deeper researches into nature, he would consider her both seriously and at leisure, that he would reflect upon himself also, and knowing what proportion there is….] Let man then contemplate the whole of nature in her full and grand majesty, and turn his vision from the low objects which surround him. Let him gaze on that brilliant light, set like an eternal lamp to illumine the universe; let the earth appear to him a point in comparison with the vast circle described by the sun; and let him wonder at the fact that this vast circle is itself but a very fine point in comparison with that described by the stars in their revolution round the firmament. But if our view be arrested there, let our imagination pass beyond; it will sooner exhaust the power of conception than nature that of supplying material for conception. The whole visible world is only an imperceptible atom in the ample bosom of nature. No idea approaches it. We may enlarge our conceptions beyond all imaginable space; we only produce atoms in comparison with the reality of things. It is an infinite sphere, the centre of which is everywhere, the circumference nowhere. In short it is the greatest sensible mark of the almighty power of God, that imagination loses itself in that thought.
Returning to himself, let man consider
what he is in comparison with all existence; let him regard himself
as lost in this remote corner of nature; and from the little cell in
which he finds himself lodged, I mean the universe, let him estimate
at their true value the earth, kingdoms, cities, and himself. What is
a man in the Infinite?
But to show him another prodigy
equally astonishing, let him examine the most delicate things he
knows. Let a mite be given him, with its minute body and parts
incomparably more minute, limbs with their joints, veins in the
limbs, blood in the veins, humours in the blood, drops in the
humours, vapours in the drops. Dividing these last things again, let
him exhaust his powers of conception, and let the last object at
which he can arrive be now that of our discourse. Perhaps he will
think that here is the smallest point in nature. I will let him see
therein a new abyss. I will paint for him not only the visible
universe, but all that he can conceive of nature’s immensity in the
womb of this abridged atom. Let him see therein an infinity of
universes, each of which has its firmament, its planets, its earth,
in the same proportion as in the visible world; in each earth
animals, and in the last mites, in which he will find again all that
the first had, finding still in these others the same thing without
end and without cessation. Let him lose himself in wonders as amazing
in their littleness as the others in their vastness. For who will not
be astounded at the fact that our body, which a little ago was
imperceptible, in the universe, itself imperceptible in the bosom of
the whole, is now a colossus, a world, or rather a whole, in respect
of the nothingness which we cannot reach? He who regards himself in
this light will be afraid of himself, and observing himself sustained
in the body given him by nature between those two abysses of the
Infinite and Nothing, will tremble at the sight of these marvels; and
I think that, as his curiosity changes into admiration, he will be
more disposed to contemplate them in silence than to examine them
with presumption.
For in fact what is man in nature? A
Nothing in comparison with the Infinite, an All in comparison with
the Nothing, a mean between nothing and everything. Since he is
infinitely removed from comprehending the extremes, the end of things
and their beginning are hopelessly hidden from him in an impenetrable
secret; he is equally incapable of seeing the Nothing from which he
was made, and the Infinite in which he is swallowed up.
What will he do then, but perceive the
appearance of the middle of things, in an eternal despair of knowing
either their beginning or their end. All things proceed from the
Nothing, and are borne towards the Infinite. Who will follow these
marvellous processes? The Author of these wonders understands them.
None other can do so.
Through failure to contemplate these
Infinites, men have rashly rushed into the examination of nature, as
though they bore some proportion to her. It is strange that they have
wished to understand the beginnings of things, and thence to arrive
at the knowledge of the whole, with a presumption as infinite as
their object. For surely this design cannot be formed without
presumption or without a capacity infinite like nature.
If we are well-informed, we understand
that, as nature has graven her image and that of her Author on all
things, they almost all partake of her double infinity. Thus we see
that all the sciences are infinite in the extent of their researches.
For who doubts that geometry, for instance, has an infinite infinity
of problems to solve? They are also infinite in the multitude and
fineness of their premises; for it is clear that those which are put
forward as ultimate are not self-supporting, but are based on others
which, again having others for their support, do not permit of
finality. But we represent some as ultimate for reason, in the same
way as in regard to material objects we call that an indivisible
point beyond which our senses can no longer perceive anything,
although by its nature it is infinitely divisible.
Of these two Infinites of science,
that of greatness is the most palpable, and hence a few persons have
pretended to know all things. “I will speak of the whole,” said
Democritus.
But the infinitely
little is the least obvious. Philosophers have much oftener claimed
to have reached it, and it is here they have all stumbled. This has
given rise to such common titles as First Principles,
Principles of Philosophy, and the like, as ostentatious in
fact, though not in appearance, as that one which blinds us, De
omni scibili. 2
We naturally believe ourselves far
more capable of reaching the centre of things than of embracing their
circumference. The visible extent of the world visibly exceeds us,
but as we exceed little things, we think ourselves more capable of
knowing them. And yet we need no less capacity for attaining the
Nothing than the All. Infinite capacity is required for both, and it
seems to me that whoever shall have understood the ultimate
principles of being might also attain to the knowledge of the
Infinite. The one depends on the other, and one leads to the other.
These extremes meet and reunite by force of distance, and find each
other in God, and in God alone.
Let us then take our compass; we are
something, and we are not everything. The nature of our existence
hides from us the knowledge of first beginnings which are born of the
Nothing; and the littleness of our being conceals from us the sight
of the Infinite.
Our intellect holds the same position
in the world of thought as our body occupies in the expanse of
nature.
Limited as we are
in every way, this state which holds the mean between two extremes is
present in all our impotence. Our senses perceive no extreme. Too
much sound deafens us; too much light dazzles us; too great distance
or proximity hinders our view. Too great length and too great brevity
of discourse tend to obscurity; too much truth is paralysing (I know
some who cannot understand that to take four from nothing leaves
nothing). First principles are too self-evident for us; too much
pleasure disagrees with us. Too many concords are annoying in music;
too many benefits irritate us; we wish to have the wherewithal to
over-pay our debts. Beneficia eo usque læta sunt dum
videntur exsolvi posse; ubi multum antevenere, pro gratia odium
redditur. 3 We feel neither
extreme heat nor extreme cold. Excessive qualities are prejudicial to
us and not perceptible by the senses; we do not feel but suffer them.
Extreme youth and extreme age hinder the mind, as also too much and
too little education. In short, extremes are for us as though they
were not, and we are not within their notice. The escape us, or we
them.
This is our true state; this is what
makes us incapable of certain knowledge and of absolute ignorance. We
sail within a vast sphere, ever drifting in uncertainty, driven from
end to end. When we think to attach ourselves to any point and to
fasten to it, it wavers and leaves us; and if we follow it, it eludes
our grasp, slips past us, and vanishes for ever. Nothing stays for
us. This is our natural condition, and yet most contrary to our
inclination; we burn with desire to find solid ground and an ultimate
sure foundation whereon to build a tower reaching to the Infinite.
But our whole groundwork cracks, and the earth opens to abysses.
Let us therefore not look for
certainty and stability. Our reason is always deceived by fickle
shadows; nothing can fix the finite between the two Infinites, which
both enclose and fly from it.
If this be well understood, I think
that we shall remain at rest, each in the state wherein nature has
placed him. As this sphere which has fallen to us as our lot is
always distant from either extreme, what matters it that man should
have a little more knowledge of the universe? If he has it, he but
gets a little higher. Is he not always infinitely removed from the
end, and is not the duration of our life equally removed from
eternity, even if it lasts ten years longer?
In comparison with these Infinites all
finites are equal and I see no reason for fixing our imagination on
one more than on another. The only comparison which we make of
ourselves to the finite is painful to us.
If man made himself the first object
of study, he would see how incapable he is of going further. How can
a part know the whole? But he may perhaps aspire to know at least the
parts to which he bears some proportion. But the parts of the world
are all so related and linked to one another, that I believe it
impossible to know one without the other and without the whole.
Man, for instance, is related to all
he knows. He needs a place wherein to abide, time through which to
live, motion in order to live, elements to compose him, warmth and
food to nourish him, air to breathe. He sees light; he feels bodies;
in short, he is in a dependant alliance with everything. To know man,
then, it is necessary to know how it happens that he needs air to
live, and, to know the air, we must know how it is thus related to
the life of man, etc. Flame cannot exist without air; therefore to
understand the one, we must understand the other.
Since everything then is cause and
effect, dependant and supporting, mediate and immediate, and all is
held together by a natural though imperceptible chain, which binds
together things most distant and most different, I hold it equally
impossible to know the parts without knowing the whole, and to know
the whole without knowing the parts in detail.
[The eternity of things in itself or
in God must also astonish our brief duration. The fixed and constant
immobility of nature, in comparison with the continual change which
goes on within us, must have the same effect.]
And what completes our incapability of
knowing things, is the fact that they are simple, and that we are
composed of two opposite natures, different in kind, soul and body.
For it is impossible that our rational part should be other than
spiritual; and if any one maintain that we are simply corporeal, this
would far more exclude us from the knowledge of things, there being
nothing so inconceivable as to say that matter knows itself. It is
impossible to imagine how it should know itself.
So if we are simply material, we can
know nothing at all; and if we are composed of mind and matter, we
cannot know perfectly things which are simple, whether spiritual or
corporeal. Hence it comes that almost all philosophers have confused
ideas of things, and speak of material things in spiritual terms, and
of spiritual things in material terms. For they say boldly that
bodies have a tendency to fall, that they seek after their centre,
that they fly from destruction, that they fear the void, that they
have inclinations, sympathies, antipathies, all of which attributes
pertain only to mind. And in speaking of minds, they consider them as
in a place, and attribute to them movement from one place to another;
and these are qualities which belong only to bodies.
Instead of receiving the ideas of
these things in their purity, we colour them with our own qualities,
and stamp with our composite being all the simple things which we
contemplate.
Who would not
think, seeing us compose all things of mind and body, but that this
mixture would be quite intelligible to us? Yet it is the very thing
we least understand. Man is to himself the most wonderful object in
nature; for he cannot conceive what the body is, still less what the
mind is, and least of all how a body should be united to a mind. This
is the consummation of his difficulties, and yet it is his very
being. Modus quo corporibus adhærent spiritus comprehendi ab
hominibus non potest, et hoc tamen homo est. 4
Finally, to complete the proof of our weakness, I shall conclude with
these two considerations…
73
[But perhaps this subject goes beyond the capacity of reason. Let us therefore examine her solutions to problems within her powers. If there be anything to which her own interest must have made her apply herself most seriously, it is the inquiry into her own sovereign good. Let us see, then, wherein these strong and clear-sighted souls have placed it, and whether they agree.
One
says that the sovereign good consists in virtue, another in pleasure,
another in the knowledge of nature, another in truth, Felix
qui potuit rerum cognoscere causas, 5 another in
total ignorance, another in indolence, others in disregarding
appearances, another in wondering at nothing, nihil admirari
prope res una quæ possit facere et servare beatum, 6 and
the true sceptics in their indifference, doubt, and perpetual
suspense, and others, wiser, think to find a better definition. We
are well satisfied.
To transpose after the laws to the
following title.
We must see if this fine philosophy have gained nothing
certain from so long and so intent study; perhaps at least the soul
will know itself. Let us hear the rulers of the world on this
subject. What have they thought of her substance? 394. 7 Have
they been more fortunate in locating her? 395. 8 What
have they found out about her origin, duration, and departure? 399. 9
Is then the soul
too noble a subject for their feeble lights? Let us then abase her to
matter and see if she knows whereof is made the very body which she
animates, and those others which she contemplates and moves at her
will. What have those great dogmatists, who are ignorant of nothing,
known of this matter? Harum sententiarum, 393. 10
This would doubtless suffice, if
reason were reasonable. She is reasonable enough to admit that she
has been unable to find anything durable, but she does not yet
despair of reaching it; she is as ardent as ever in this search, and
is confident she has within her the necessary powers for this
conquest. We must therefore conclude, and, after having examined her
powers in their effects, observe them in themselves, and see if she
has a nature and a grasp capable of laying hold of the truth.]
74
A letter on the foolishness of human knowledge and philosophy.
This letter before Diversion.
280 kinds of sovereign
good in Montaigne.
75
Part I., 1, 2, c. 1, section 4.
[Probability.—it will not be
difficult to put the case a stage lower, and make it appear
ridiculous. To begin at the very beginning.] What is more absurd than
to say that lifeless bodies have passions, fears, hatreds,—that
insensible bodies, lifeless and incapable of life, have passions
which presuppose at least a sensitive soul to feel them, nay more,
that the object of their dread is the void? What is there in the void
that could make them afraid? Nothing is more shallow and ridiculous.
This is not all; it is said that they have in themselves a source of
movement to shun the void. Have they arms, legs, muscles, nerves?
76
To write against those who made too profound a study of science. Descartes.
77
I cannot forgive Descartes. In all his philosophy he would have been quite willing to dispense with God. But he had to make Him give a fillip to set the world in motion; beyond this, he has no further need of God.
78
Descartes useless and uncertain.
79
[Descartes.—We must say summarily: “This is made by figure and motion,” for it is true. But to say what these are, and to compose the machine, is ridiculous. For it is useless, uncertain, and painful. And were it true, we do not think all philosophy is worth one hour of pain.]
80
How comes it that a cripple does not offend us, but that a fool does? Because a cripple recognizes that we walk straight, whereas a fool declares that it is we who are silly; if it were not so, we should feel pity and not anger.
Epictetus asks still more strongly:
“Why are we not angry if we are told that we have a headache, and
why are we angry if we are told that we reason badly, or choose
wrongly?” The reason is that we are quite certain that we have not
a headache, or are not lame, but we are not so sure that we make a
true choice. So having assurance only because we see with our whole
sight, it puts us into suspense and surprise when another with his
whole sight sees the opposite, and still more so when a thousand
others deride our choice. For we must prefer our own lights to those
of so many others, and that is bold and difficult. There is never
this contradiction in the feelings towards a cripple.
81
It is natural for the mind to believe, and for the will to love; so that, for want of true objects, they must attach themselves to false.
Note
1. “Animals run.”
Note
2. “Concerning everything knowable”—the title under
which Pico della Mirandola announced the 900 propositions which he
undertook to defend in 1486.
Note
3. “Benefits are pleasant while it seems possible to
requite them; when they become much greater, they produce hatred
rather than gratitude.”—Tacitus.
Note
4. “The manner in which spirits are united to bodies
cannot be understood by men, yet such is man.”—St. Augustine.
Note
6. “To wonder at nothing is almost the only thing which
can make and keep a man happy.”—Horace.
Note
12. “To wonder at nothing is almost the only thing which
can make and keep a man happy.”—Horace.
0 comments