What Is Good Taste?
January 12, 2021Edmund Burke |
Edmund Burke (1729–1797). On Taste.
A Turkish sultan, relates Burke, when shown a picture of the beheaded John the Baptist, praised many things, but pointed out one gruesome defect. Did this observation show the sultan to be an inferior judge of art?
ON a superficial view,
we may seem to differ very widely from each other in our reasonings,
and no less in our pleasures: but notwithstanding this difference,
which I think to be rather apparent than real, it is probable that
the standard both of reason and taste is the same in all human
creatures. For if there were not some principles of judgment as well
as of sentiment common to all mankind, no hold could possibly be
taken either on their reason or their passions, sufficient to
maintain the ordinary correspondence of life. It appears indeed to be
generally acknowledged, that with regard to truth and falsehood there
is something fixed. We find people in their disputes continually
appealing to certain tests and standards, which are allowed on all
sides, and are supposed to be established in our common nature. But
there is not the same obvious concurrence in any uniform or settled
principles which relate to taste. It is even commonly supposed that
this delicate and aerial faculty, which seems too volatile to endure
even the chains of a definition, cannot be properly tried by any
test, nor regulated by any standard. There is so continual a call for
the exercise of the reasoning faculty, and it is so much strengthened
by perpetual contention, that certain maxims of right reason seem to
be tacitly settled amongst the most ignorant. The learned have
improved on this rude science, and reduced those maxims into a
system. If taste has not been so happily cultivated, it was not that
the subject was barren, but that the labourers were few or negligent;
for, to say the truth, there are not the same interesting motives to
impel us to fix the one, which urge us to ascertain the other. And,
after all, if men differ in their opinion concerning such matters,
their difference is not attended with the same important
consequences; else I make no doubt but that the logic of taste, if I
may be allowed the expression, might very possibly be as well
digested, and we might come to discuss matters of this nature with as
much certainty, as those which seem more immediately within the
province of mere reason. And indeed, it is very necessary, at the
entrance into such an inquiry as our present, to make this point as
clear as possible; for if taste has no fixed principles, if the
imagination is not affected according to some invariable and certain
laws, our labour is likely to be employed to very little purpose; as
it must be judged a useless, if not an absurd undertaking, to lay
down rules for caprice, and to set up for a legislator of whims and
fancies.
The term taste,
like all other figurative terms, is not extremely accurate; the thing
which we understand by it is far from a simple and determinate idea
in the minds of most men, and it is therefore liable to uncertainty
and confusion. I have no great opinion of a definition, the
celebrated remedy for the cure of this disorder. For, when we define,
we seem in danger of circumscribing nature within the bounds of our
own notions, which we often take up by hazard, or embrace on trust,
or form out of a limited and partial consideration of the object
before us; instead of extending our ideas to take in all that nature
comprehends, according to her manner of combining. We are limited in
our inquiry by the strict laws to which we have submitted at our
setting out.
—Circa vilem
patulumque morabimur orbem,
Unde pudor proferre
pedem vetat aut operis lex.
A definition may be
very exact, and yet go but a very little way towards informing us of
the nature of the thing defined; but let the virtue of a definition
be what it will, in the order of things, it seems rather to follow
than to precede our inquiry, of which it ought to be considered as
the result. It must be acknowledged, that the methods of disquisition
and teaching may be sometimes different, and on very good reason
undoubtedly; but, for my part, I am convinced that the method of
teaching which approaches most nearly to the method of investigation
is incomparably the best; since, not content with serving up a few
barren and lifeless truths, it leads to the stock on which they grew;
it tends to set the reader himself in the track of invention, and to
direct him into those paths in which the author has made his own
discoveries, if he should be so happy as to have made any that are
valuable.
But to cut off all
pretence for cavilling, I mean by the word Taste no more than that
faculty or those faculties of the mind, which are affected with, or
which form a judgment of, the works of imagination and the elegant
arts. This is, I think the most general idea of that word, and what
is the least connected with any particular theory. And my point in
this inquiry is, to find whether there are any principles, on which
the imagination is affected, so common to all, so grounded and
certain, as to supply the means of reasoning satisfactorily about
them. And such principles of taste I fancy there are; however
paradoxical it may seem to those, who on a superficial view imagine,
that there is so great a diversity of tastes, both in kind and
degree, that nothing can be more indeterminate.
All the natural
powers in man, which I know, that are conversant about external
objects, are the senses; the imagination; and the judgment. And first
with regard to the senses. We do and we must suppose, that as the
conformation of their organs is nearly or altogether the same in all
men, so the manner of perceiving external objects is in all men the
same, or with little difference. We are satisfied that what appears
to be light to one eye, appears light to another; that what seems
sweet to one palate, is sweet to another; that what is dark and
bitter to this man, is likewise dark and bitter to that; and we
conclude in the same manner of great and little, hard and soft, hot
and cold, rough and smooth, and indeed of all the natural qualities
and affections of bodies. If we suffer ourselves to imagine, that
their senses present to different men different images of things,
this sceptical proceeding will make every sort of reasoning on every
subject vain and frivolous, even that sceptical reasoning itself
which had persuaded us to entertain a doubt concerning the agreement
of our perceptions. But as there will be little doubt that bodies
present similar images to the whole species, it must necessarily be
allowed, that the pleasures and the pains which every object excites
in one man, it must raise in all mankind, whilst it operates
naturally, simply, and by its proper powers only; for if we deny
this, we must imagine that the same cause, operating in the same
manner, and on subjects of the same kind, will produce different
effects; which would be highly absurd. Let us first consider this
point in the sense of taste, and the rather, as the faculty in
question has taken its name from that sense. All men are agreed to
call vinegar sour, honey sweet, and aloes bitter; and as they are all
agreed in finding these qualities in those objects, they do not in
the least differ concerning their effects with regard to pleasure and
pain. They all concur in calling sweetness pleasant, and sourness and
bitterness unpleasant. Here there is no diversity in their
sentiments; and that there is not, appears fully from the consent of
all men in the metaphors which are taken from the sense of taste. A
sour temper, bitter expressions, bitter curses, a bitter fate, are
terms well and strongly understood by all. And we are altogether as
well understood when we say, a sweet disposition, a sweet person, a
sweet condition, and the like. It is confessed, that custom and some
other causes have made many deviations from the natural pleasures or
pains which belong to these several tastes: but then the power of
distinguishing between the natural and the acquired relish remains to
the very last. A man frequently comes to prefer the taste of tobacco
to that of sugar, and the flavour of vinegar to that of milk; but
this makes no confusion in tastes, whilst he is sensible that the
tobacco and vinegar are not sweet, and whilst he knows that habit
alone has reconciled his palate to these alien pleasures. Even with
such a person we may speak, and with sufficient precision, concerning
tastes. But should any man be found who declares, that to him tobacco
has a taste like sugar, and that he cannot distinguish between milk
and vinegar; or that tobacco and vinegar are sweet, milk bitter, and
sugar sour; we immediately conclude that the organs of this man are
out of order, and that his palate is utterly vitiated. We are as far
from conferring with such a person upon tastes, as from reasoning
concerning the relations of quantity with one who should deny that
all the parts together were equal to the whole. We do not call a man
of this kind wrong in his notions, but absolutely mad. Exceptions of
this sort, in either way, do not at all impeach our general rule, nor
make us conclude that men have various principles concerning the
relations of quantity or the taste of things. So that when it is
said, taste cannot be disputed, it can only mean, that no one can
strictly answer what pleasure or pain some particular man may find
from the taste of some particular thing. This indeed cannot be
disputed; but we may dispute, and with sufficient clearness too,
concerning the things which are naturally pleasing or disagreeable to
the sense. But when we talk of any peculiar or acquired relish, then
we must know the habits, the prejudices, or the distempers of this
particular man, and we must draw our conclusion from those.
This agreement of
mankind is not confined to the taste solely. The principle of
pleasure derived from sight is the same in all. Light is more
pleasing than darkness. Summer, when the earth is clad in green, when
the heavens are serene and bright, is more agreeable than winter,
when everything makes a different appearance. I never remember that
anything beautiful, whether a man, a beast, a bird, or a plant, was
ever shown, though it were to a hundred people, that they did not all
immediately agree that it was beautiful, though some might have
thought that it fell short of their expectation, or that other things
were still finer. I believe no man thinks a goose to be more
beautiful than a swan, or imagines that what they call a Friesland
hen excels a peacock. It must be observed, too, that the pleasures of
the sight are not near so complicated, and confused, and altered by
unnatural habits and associations, as the pleasures of the taste are;
because the pleasures of the sight more commonly acquiesce in
themselves; and are not so often altered by considerations which are
independent of the sight itself. But things do not spontaneously
present themselves to the palate as they do to the sight; they are
generally applied to it, either as food or as medicine; and, from the
qualities which they possess for nutritive or medicinal purposes,
they often form the palate by degrees, and by force of these
associations. Thus opium is pleasing to Turks, on account of the
agreeable delirium it produces. Tobacco is the delight of Dutchmen,
as it diffuses a torpor and pleasing stupefaction. Fermented spirits
please our common people, because they banish care, and all
consideration of future or present evils. All of these would lie
absolutely neglected if their properties had originally gone no
further than the taste; but all these together, with tea and coffee,
and some other things, have passed from the apothecary’s shop to
our tables, and were taken for health long before they were thought
of for pleasure. The effect of the drug has made us use it
frequently; and frequent use, combined with the agreeable effect, has
made the taste itself at last agreeable. But this does not in the
least perplex our reasoning; because we distinguish to the last the
acquired from the natural relish. In describing the taste of an
unknown fruit, you would scarcely say that it had a sweet and
pleasant flavour like tobacco, opium, or garlic, although you spoke
to those who were in the constant use of these drugs, and had great
pleasure in them. There is in all men sufficient remembrance of the
original natural causes of pleasure, to enable them to bring all
things offered to their senses to that standard, and to regulate
their feelings and opinions by it. Suppose one who had so vitiated
his palate as to take more pleasure in the taste of opium than in
that of butter or honey, to be presented with a bolus of squills;
there is hardly any doubt but that he would prefer the butter or
honey to this nauseous morsel, or to any bitter drug to which he had
not been accustomed; which proves that his palate was naturally like
that of other men in all things, that it is still like the palate of
other men in many things, and only vitiated in some particular
points. For in judging of any new thing, even of a taste similar to
that which he has been formed by habit to like, he finds his palate
affected in a natural manner, and on the common principles. Thus the
pleasure of all the senses, of the sight, and even of the taste, that
most ambiguous of the senses, is the same in all, high and low,
learned and unlearned.
Besides the ideas,
with their annexed pains and pleasures, which are presented by the
sense; the mind of man possesses a sort of creative power of its own;
either in representing at pleasure the images of things in the order
and manner in which they were received by the senses, or in combining
those images in a new manner, and according to a different order.
This power is called imagination; and to this belongs whatever is
called wit, fancy, invention, and the like. But it must be observed,
that this power of the imagination is incapable of producing anything
absolutely new; it can only vary the disposition of those ideas which
it has received from the senses. Now the imagination is the most
extensive province of pleasure and pain, as it is the region of our
fears and our hopes, and of all our passions that are connected with
them; and whatever is calculated to affect the imagination with these
commanding ideas, by force of any original natural impression, must
have the same power pretty equally over all men. For since the
imagination is only the representation of the senses, it can only be
pleased or displeased with the images, from the same principle on
which the sense is pleased or displeased with the realities; and
consequently there must be just as close an agreement in the
imaginations as in the senses of men. A little attention will
convince us that this must of necessity be the case.
But in the
imagination, besides the pain or pleasure arising from the properties
of the natural object, a pleasure is perceived from the resemblance
which the imitation has to the original: the imagination, I conceive,
can have no pleasure but what results from one or other of these
causes. And these causes operate pretty uniformly upon all men,
because they operate by principles in nature, and which are not
derived from any particular habits or advantages. Mr. Locke very
justly and finely observes of wit, that it is chiefly conversant in
tracing resemblances: he remarks, at the same time, that the business
of judgment is rather in finding differences. It may perhaps appear,
on this supposition, that there is no material distinction between
the wit and the judgment, as they both seem to result from different
operations of the same faculty of comparing. But in reality,
whether they are or are not dependent on the same power of the mind,
they differ so very materially in many respects, that a perfect union
of wit and judgment is one of the rarest things in the world. When
two distinct objects are unlike to each other, it is only what we
expect; things are in their common way; and therefore they make no
impression on the imagination: but when two distinct objects have a
resemblance, we are struck, we attend to them, and we are pleased.
The mind of man has naturally a far greater alacrity and satisfaction
in tracing resemblances than in searching for differences: because by
making resemblances we produce new images; we unite, we create, we
enlarge our stock; but in making distinctions we offer no food at all
to the imagination; the task itself is more severe and irksome, and
what pleasure we derive from it is something of a negative and
indirect nature. A piece of news is told me in the morning; this,
merely as a piece of news, as a fact added to my stock, gives me some
pleasure. In the evening I find there was nothing in it. What do I
gain by this, but the dissatisfaction to find that I have been
imposed upon? Hence it is that men are much more naturally inclined
to belief than to incredulity. And it is upon this principle, that
the most ignorant and barbarous nations have frequently excelled in
similitudes, comparisons, metaphors, and allegories, who have been
weak and backward in distinguishing and sorting their ideas. And it
is for a reason of this kind, that Homer and the Oriental writers,
though very fond of similitudes, and though they often strike out
such as are truly admirable, seldom take care to have them exact;
that is, they are taken with the general resemblance, they paint it
strongly, and they take no notice of the difference which may be
found between the things compared.
Now, as the
pleasure of resemblance is that which principally flatters the
imagination, all men are nearly equal in this point, as far as their
knowledge of the things represented or compared extends. The
principle of this knowledge is very much accidental, as it depends
upon experience and observation, and not on the strength or weakness
of any natural faculty; and it is from this difference in knowledge,
that what we commonly, though with no great exactness, call a
difference in taste proceeds. A man to whom sculp ture is new, sees a
barber’s block, or some ordinary piece of statuary, he is
immediately struck and pleased, because he sees something like a
human figure; and, entirely taken up with this likeness, he does not
at all attend to its defects. No person, I believe, at the first time
of seeing a piece of imitation ever did. Some time after, we suppose
that this novice lights upon a more artificial work of the same
nature; he now begins to look with contempt on what he admired at
first; not that he admired it even then for its unlikeness to a man,
but for that general, though inaccurate, resemblance which it bore to
the human figure. What he admired at different times in these so
different figures, is strictly the same; and though his knowledge is
improved, his taste is not altered. Hitherto his mistake was from a
want of knowledge in art; and this arose from his inexperience; but
he may be still deficient from a want of knowledge in nature. For it
is possible that the man in question may stop here, and that the
masterpiece of a great hand may please him no more than the middling
performance of a vulgar artist: and this not for want of better or
higher relish, but because all men do not observe with sufficient
accuracy on the human figure to enable them to judge properly of an
imitation of it. And that the critical taste does not depend upon a
superior principle in men, but upon superior knowledge, may appear
from several instances. The story of the ancient painter and the
shoemaker is very well known. The shoemaker set the painter right
with regard to some mistakes he had made in the shoe of one of his
figures, and which the painter, who had not made such accurate
observations on shoes, and was content with a general resemblance,
had never observed. But this was no impeachment to the taste of the
painter; it only showed some want of knowledge in the art of making
shoes. Let us imagine, that an anatomist had come into the painter’s
working-room. His piece is in general well done, the figure in
question in a good attitude, and the parts well adjusted to their
various movements; yet the anatomist, critical in his art, may
observe the swell of some muscle not quite just in the peculiar
action of the figure. Here the anatomist observes what the painter
had not observed; and he passes by what the shoemaker had remarked.
But a want of the last critical knowledge in anatomy no more
reflected on the natural good taste of the painter or of any common
observer of his piece, than the want of an exact knowledge in the
formation of a shoe. A fine piece of a decollated head of St. John
the Baptist was shown to a Turkish emperor; he praised many things,
but he observed one defect; he observed that the skin did not shrink
from the wounded part of the neck. The sultan on this occasion,
though his observation was very just, discovered no more natural
taste than the painter who executed this piece, or than a thousand
European connoisseurs, who probably never would have made the same
observation. His Turkish Majesty had indeed been well acquainted with
that terrible spectacle, which the others could only have represented
in their imagination. On the subject of their dislike there is a
difference between all these people, arising from the different kinds
and degrees of their knowledge; but there is something in common to
the painter, the shoemaker, the anatomist, and the Turkish emperor,
the pleasure arising from a natural object, so far as each perceives
it justly imitated; the satisfaction in seeing an agreeable figure;
the sympathy proceeding from a striking and affecting incident. So
far as taste is natural, it is nearly common to all.
In poetry, and
other pieces of imagination, the same parity may be observed. It is
true, that one man is charmed with Don Bellianis, and reads Virgil
coldly; whilst another is transported with the Eneid, and leaves Don
Bellianis to children. These two men seem to have a taste very
different from each other; but in fact they differ very little. In
both these pieces, which inspire such opposite sentiments, a tale
exciting admiration is told; both are full of action, both are
passionate; in both are voyages, battles, triumphs, and continual
changes of fortune. The admirer of Don Bellianis perhaps does not
understand the refined language of the Eneid, who, if it was degraded
into the style of the Pilgrim’s Progress, might feel it in all its
energy, on the same principle which made him an admirer of Don
Bellianis.
In his favourite
author he is not shocked with the continual breaches of probability,
the confusion of times, the offences against manners, the trampling
upon geography; for he knows nothing of geography and chronology, and
he has never examined the grounds of probability. He perhaps reads of
a shipwreck on the coast of Bohemia; wholly taken up with so
interesting an event, and only solicitous for the fate of his hero,
he is not in the least troubled at this extravagant blunder. For why
should he be shocked at a shipwreck on the coast of Bohemia, who does
not know but that Bohemia may be an island in the Atlantic ocean? and
after all, what reflection is this on the natural good taste of the
person here supposed?
So far then as
taste belongs to the imagination, its principle is the same in all
men; there is no difference in the manner of their being affected,
nor in the causes of the affection; but in the degree there is a
difference, which arises from two causes principally; either from a
greater degree of natural sensibility, or from a closer and longer
attention to the object. To illustrate this by the procedure of the
senses, in which the same difference is found, let us suppose a very
smooth marble table to be set before two men; they both perceive it
to be smooth; and they are both pleased with it because of this
quality. So far they agree. But suppose another, and after that
another table, the latter still smoother than the former, to be set
before them. It is now very probable that these men, who are so
agreed upon what is smooth, and in the pleasure from thence, will
disagree when they come to settle which table has the advantage in
point of polish. Here is indeed the great difference between tastes,
when men come to compare the excess or diminution of things which are
judged by degree and not by measure. Nor is it easy, when such a
difference arises, to settle the point, if the excess or diminution
be not glaring. If we differ in opinion about two quantities, we can
have recourse to a common measure, which may decide the question with
the utmost exactness; and this, I take it, is what gives mathematical
knowledge a greater certainty than any other. But in things whose
excess is not judged by greater or smaller, as smoothness and
roughness, hardness and softness, darkness and light, the shades of
colours, all these are very easily distinguished when the difference
is any way considerable, but not when it is minute, for want of some
common measures, which perhaps may never come to be discovered. In
these nice cases, supposing the acuteness of the sense equal, the
greater attention and habit in such things will have the advantage.
In the question about the tables, the marble-polisher will
unquestionably determine the most accurately. But notwithstanding
this want of a common measure for settling many disputes relative to
the senses, and their representative the imagination, we find that
the principles are the same in all, and that there is no disagreement
until we come to examine into the pre-eminence or difference of
things, which brings us within the province of the judgment.
So long as we are
conversant with the sensible qualities of things, hardly any more
than the imagination seems concerned; little more also than the
imagination seems concerned when the passions are represented,
because by the force of natural sympathy they are felt in all men
without any recourse to reasoning, and their justness recognized in
every breast. Love, grief, fear, anger, joy, all these passions have,
in their turns, affected every mind; and they do not affect it in an
arbitrary or casual manner, but upon certain, natural, and uniform
principles. But as many of the works of imagination are not confined
to the representation of sensible objects, nor to efforts upon the
passions, but extend themselves to the manners, the characters, the
actions, and designs of men, their relations, their virtues, and
vices, they come within the province of the judgment, which is
improved by attention, and by the habit of reasoning. All these make
a very considerable part of what are considered as the objects of
taste; and Horace sends us to the schools of philosophy and the world
for our instruction in them. Whatever certainty is to be acquired in
morality and the science of life; just the same degree of certainty
have we in what relates to them in the works of imitation. Indeed it
is for the most part in our skill in manners, and in the observances
of time and place, and of decency in general, which is only to be
learned in those schools to which Horace recommends us, that what is
called taste, by way of distinction, consists; and which is in
reality no other than a more refined judgment. On the whole it
appears to me, that what is called taste, in its most general
acceptation, is not a simple idea, but is partly made up of a
perception of the primary pleasures of sense, of the secondary
pleasures of the imagination, and of the conclusions of the reasoning
faculty, concerning the various relations to these, and concerning
the human passions, manners, and actions. All this is requisite to
form taste, and the ground-work of all these is the same in the human
mind; for as the senses are the great originals of all our ideas, and
consequently of all our pleasures, if they are not uncertain and
arbitrary, the whole ground-work of taste is common to all, and
therefore there is a sufficient foundation for a conclusive reasoning
on these matters.
Whilst we consider
taste merely according to its nature and species, we shall find its
principles entirely uniform; but the degree in which these principles
prevail in the several individuals of mankind, is altogether as
different as the principles themselves are similar. For sensibility
and judgment, which are the qualities that compose what we commonly
call a taste, vary exceedingly in various people. From a defect in
the former of these qualities arises a want of taste; a weakness in
the latter constitutes a wrong or a bad one. There are some men
formed with feelings so blunt, with tempers so cold and phlegmatic,
that they can hardly be said to be awake during the whole course of
their lives. Upon such persons the most striking objects make but a
faint and obscure impression. There are others so continually in the
agitation of gross and merely sensual pleasures, or so occupied in
the low drudgery of avarice, or so heated in the chase of honours and
distinction, that their minds, which had been used continually to the
storms of these violent and tempestuous passions, can hardly be put
in motion by the delicate and refined play of the imagination. These
men, though from a different cause, become as stupid and insensible
as the former; but whenever either of these happen to be struck with
any natural elegance or greatness, or with these qualities in any
work of art, they are moved upon the same principle.
The cause of a
wrong taste is a defect of judgment. And this may arise from a
natural weakness of understanding, (in whatever the strength of that
faculty may consist,) or, which is much more commonly the case, it
may arise from a want of proper and well-directed exercise, which
alone can make it strong and ready. Besides that ignorance,
inattention, prejudice, rashness, levity, obstinacy, in short, all
those passions, and all those vices, which pervert the judgment in
other matters, prejudice it no less in this its more refined and
elegant province. These causes produce different opinions upon
everything which is an object of the understanding, without inducing
us to suppose that there are no settled principles of reason. And
indeed, on the whole, one may observe that there is rather less
difference upon matters of taste among mankind, than upon most of
those which depend upon the naked reason; and that men are far better
agreed on the excellency of a description in Virgil, than on the
truth or falsehood of a theory of Aristotle.
A rectitude of
judgment in the arts, which may be called a good taste, does in a
great measure depend upon sensibility; because, if the mind has no
bent to the pleasures of the imagination, it will never apply itself
sufficiently to works of that species to acquire a competent
knowledge in them. But, though a degree of sensibility is requisite
to form a good judgment, yet a good judgment does not necessarily
arise from a quick sensibility of pleasure; it frequently happens
that a very poor judge, merely by force of a greater complexional
sensibility, is more affected by a very poor piece, than the best
judge by the most perfect; for as everything new, extraordinary,
grand, or passionate, is well calculated to affect such a person, and
that the faults do not affect him, his pleasure is more pure and
unmixed; and as it is merely a pleasure of the imagination, it is
much higher than any which is derived from a rectitude of the
judgment; the judgment is for the greater part employed in throwing
stumbling-blocks in the way of the imagination, in dissipating the
scenes of its enchantment, and in tying us down to the disagreeable
yoke of our reason: for almost the only pleasure that men have in
judging better than others, consists in a sort of conscious pride and
superiority, which arises from thinking rightly; but then, this is an
indirect pleasure, a pleasure which does not immediately result from
the object which is under contemplation. In the morning of our days,
when the senses are unworn and tender, when the whole man is awake in
every part, and the gloss of novelty fresh upon all the objects that
surround us, how lively at that time are our sensations, but how
false and inaccurate the judgments we form of things? I despair of
ever receiving the same degree of pleasure from the most excellent
performances of genius, which I felt at that age from pieces which my
present judgment regards as trifling and contemptible. Every trivial
cause of pleasure is apt to affect the man of too sanguine a
complexion: his appetite is too keen to suffer his taste to be
delicate; and he is in all respects what Ovid says of himself in
love,
Molle meum levibus cor
est violabile telis,
Et semper causa est,
cur ego semper amem.
One of this character
can never be a refined judge; never what the comic poet calls
elegans formarum spectator. The excellence and force of a
composition must always be imperfectly estimated from its effect on
the minds of any, except we know the temper and character of those
minds. The most powerful effects of poetry and music have been
displayed, and perhaps are still displayed, where these arts are but
in a very low and imperfect state. The rude hearer is affected by the
principles which operate in these arts even in their rudest
condition; and he is not skillful enough to perceive the defects. But
as the arts advance towards their perfection, the science of
criticism advances with equal pace, and the pleasure of judges is
frequently interrupted by the faults which are discovered in the most
finished compositions.
Before I leave this
subject I cannot help taking notice of an opinion which many persons
entertain, as if the taste were a separate faculty of the mind, and
distinct from the judgment and imagination; a species of instinct, by
which we are struck naturally, and at the first glance, without any
previous reasoning, with the excellencies, or the defects, of a
composition. So far as the imagination and the passions are
concerned, I believe it true, that the reason is little consulted;
but where disposition, where decorum, where congruity are concerned,
in short, wherever the best taste differs from the worst, I am
convinced that the understanding operates, and nothing else; and its
operation is in reality far from being always sudden, or, when it is
sudden, it is often far from being right. Men of the best taste, by
consideration, come frequently to change these early and precipitate
judgments, which the mind, from its aversion to neutrality and doubt,
loves to form on the spot. It is known that the taste (whatever it
is) is improved exactly as we improve our judgment, by extending our
knowledge, by a steady attention to our object, and by frequent
exercise. They who have not taken these methods, if their taste
decides quickly, it is always uncertainly; and their quickness is
owing to their presumption and rashness, and not to any sudden
irradiation, that in a moment dispels all darkness from their minds.
But they who have cultivated that species of knowledge which makes
the object of taste, by degrees, and habitually, attain not only a
soundness, but a readiness of judgment, as men do by the same methods
on all other occasions. At first they are obliged to spell, but at
least they read with ease and with celerity; but this celerity of its
operation is no proof that the taste is a distinct faculty. Nobody, I
believe, has attended the course of a discussion, which turned upon
matters within the sphere of mere naked reason, but must have
observed the extreme readiness with which the whole process of the
argument is carried on, the grounds discovered, the objections raised
and answered, and the conclusions drawn from premises, with a
quickness altogether as great as the taste can be supposed to work
with; and yet where nothing but plain reason either is or can be
suspected to operate. To multiply principles for every different
appearance, is useless, and unphilosophical too in a high degree.
This matter might
be pursued much further; but it is not the extent of the subject
which must prescribe our bounds, for what subject does not branch out
to infinity? It is the nature of our particular scheme, and the
single point of view in which we consider it, which ought to put a
stop to our researches.
0 comments